Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam
![In Search of Consistency: Ethics and Animals [Human–Animal Studies] Part 10 pptx](https://storage.googleapis.com/cloud_leafy_production/1687801051708_1687801042494_343-0.png)
In Search of Consistency: Ethics and Animals [Human–Animal Studies] Part 10 pptx
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
488 chapter nine
For this reason, triage is not representative of contemporary Western
morality regarding the protection and preservation of innocent human
life. We must look elsewhere.
Perhaps sentience will be helpful in determining who will live and
who will die in our particular lifeboat scenario. To explore this possibility, we must alter our constituency: we will replace the naked
mole rat with a daisy. Is the life of this newcomer equally precious?
Must it be preserved and protected along with the life of the needleclawed bush baby and the naked mole rat?
Sentience is a morally relevant criterion in Western law—causing
serious unnecessary physical suffering to innocent human beings is
illegal. One is not allowed to starve or beat up dependents, whether
children, the elderly, or “pets.” But pain and suffering are not relevant with regard to the preservation and protection of human life.
The case of Matthew Donnelly (the physicist with cancer) provides
an apt example. He suffered terribly, to the point where he did not
wish to live any longer, yet he was kept alive against his wishes. In
contrast, Baby Theresa could not feel anything. She suffered not one
twinge, not one moment of anxiety, not one second of hunger. She
was not capable of suffering. Yet medical professionals maintained
Baby Theresa even at the expense of other children who might have
lived if they had the organs of this failing, anencephalic infant, organs
that her parents wished to donate so that other families might preserve their beloved children. Many individuals are kept alive in Western
hospitals who can feel nothing, anencephalic infants and innumerable
brain-dead patients, while each day, for want of food and medicine,
human beings who can feel and think and function, suffer and die. In
fact Western nations do not choose to allocate resources in order to
protect against suffering. Nor do we make choices in order to preserve the lives of those who can suffer in favor of those who cannot feel anything.
The Minimize Harm Maxim is an extension of morality regarding the preservation and protection of innocent human life. Human
life is preserved even if such medical efforts increase suffering. Life
is sustained even if that life suffers terribly in the process, even if
preserving that life causes others to suffer and die as a result. As it
turns out, the daisy will stay on board just as surely as any other
passenger.
Western medical practice, rooted in Western morality that protects and preserves the life of every innocent human being, does not
contemporary moral dilemmas 489
allow any human being to die so that others might live. While many
innocent human beings die of simple neglect—malnutrition, infection, diseases for which there are cures—because funds and efforts are
focused elsewhere, medical practice does not permit the loss of any
innocent human life that might be preserved. Our responsibility for
those that die of want, of neglect, is no less because they do not lie
in a hospital bed, but exploring such cases is beyond the scope of
this work.
Western law protects innocent human life. The legal system and
medical practice reflect a Western morality that holds human life to
be precious to a degree that seems beyond calculation. The Minimize
Harm Maxim, rooted in morality with regard to protecting and preserving human life, also provides no means by which to make distinctions between one life and another. As anencephalic infants aptly
demonstrate, no innocent human life is allowed to die or be killed—
even for the sake of other innocent human lives—if they might go
on living. While there are many cases in which individual doctors
permit patients to die, or even help them to do so, such cases remain
off the books. Law requires that each innocent human life be allowed to
persist for as long as possible.
For the sake of consistency and impartiality, in light of casuistry,
the life of each living entity on our unique lifeboat is as precious as
every other. The harm of exterminating any one of these five entities is equal inasmuch as the life of Baby Theresa is no more or less
morally considerable than the life of any other patient in the hospital where she lived and died. The Minimize Harm Maxim, an
extension of contemporary Western morality with regard to the preservation and protection of human life, does not discriminate between
the lives of a naked mole rat, a spectacled elephant shrew, a hyrax,
and a needle-clawed bush baby . . . even that of a daisy. Contemporary
Western ethics provide no means by which to decide who will live
and who will die on our bobbing lifeboat.
Conclusion
Western morality, as evidenced by medical practice and law, protects
every innocent human life. In the absence of any morally relevant
distinction between all human beings and all other living entities,
consistency and impartiality require the application of this same stringent morality to all life forms.
490 chapter nine
The Minimize Harm Maxim is a utopian moral theory, rooted in
consistency, extending morality between human beings to all other
living beings that have not been shown to be different in morally
relevant ways. Idealistic theories often seem extreme and unlikely,
but the Minimize Harm Maxim stands as a model of what we ought
to do if we are to be consistent and impartial. If the Minimize Harm
Maxim seems unreasonable, then our only recourse, if we are to
maintain consistency, is to reconsider our current moral ideals with
regard to protecting and preserving innocent human life.
CHAPTER TEN
REVIEW AND FUTURE DIRECTIONS
We have explored the work of four prominent scholars. Although a
critical analysis is offered for the best-known and most respected protectionist theories available, this work attests to and affirms the value
of the contribution that each of these scholars has made to the ongoing process of seeking and establishing a more consistent, compassionate morality. We have also explored an idealistic protectionist
theory based on consistency and impartiality, the Minimize Harm
Maxim. In this final chapter, we look back to the previous chapters,
and forward to what might lie ahead in the field of anymals and
ethics. What fundamental concepts have been further explored and
developed? What possible directions might be beneficial for future
work in protectionist ethics?
A. Overview
1. A Conspicuous Problem
Protectionism is an “idea that is easy to ridicule but hard to refute”
(Ryder, Animal 332).
In the West, both civil law and accepted morality protect human
conatus, the urge “to preserve our existence as persons” (P. Taylor “Inherent”
25). Predominant Western morality holds the strong conviction that
there is no legitimate reason to deny moral standing to any human
being; ideally, each human being is maintained even at tremendous
expense to society. But we do not extend this protection to anymals,
and there is a conspicuous absence of any morally legitimate reason
for treating human life differently from how we treat all other lifeforms. Moral philosophers have as yet been unable to establish any
satisfactory morally relevant difference between anymals and human
beings—one that would justify denying basic protection to other
species while maintaining such stringent protection for human life.
Yet Western ethics, as revealed in the actions of most people, persist with this flagrant inconsistency. The lives of anymals remain
492 chapter ten
almost completely unprotected. “Current legal consensus seems to
be that nearly any human interest can in principle qualify as an
acceptable justification for animal use . . . Whether there is a moral
consensus in society to this effect is more doubtful” (Orlans 317). As
a result, in the United States, “given the quantity of non-human animals suffering, the extent to which they are suffering, and the reason they are intentionally made to suffer . . . animal liberation is the
moral imperative of our time. Our . . . focus should be on ending
the suffering as efficiently and quickly as possible” (Ball 4). We are
living in a time of great moral reckoning, a time of moral reflection
leading to eye-opening moral imperatives previously overlooked. We
are, slowly, bit by bit, coming to see that our treatment of anymals
in relation to our treatment of human animals constitutes an unjustified,
flagrant inconsistency. Some have come to see that those who cling
to the maximum moral significance of human beings while denying
such significance to anymals have no philosophical leg to stand on.
We can either accept anymals into the fold or deny full moral
significance to certain human beings. Tom Regan writes:
[T]he moral beliefs we accept cannot all be true if they include two
or more inconsistent beliefs. This much, too, seems clear: our commitment to search for and, when we find them, to address such inconsistencies offers a fair indication of the seriousness with which we
respond to the challenge to develop an informed, thoughtful moral
outlook. (Defending 101)
Western morality is currently inconsistent; we are inconsistent in our
treatment of life and in our expressed “respect for life.” Peter Singer
notes:
People often say that life is sacred. They almost never mean what they
say. They do not mean, as their words seem to imply, that life itself
is sacred. If they did, killing a pig or pulling up a cabbage would be
as abhorrent to them as the murder of a human being. When people
say that life is sacred, it is human life they have in mind. But why
should human life have special value? (Writings 125)
Indeed, what is so important about us in a universe of such beauty
and diversity? Why do we persist with—and even defend—this
flagrantly immoral status quo? The cases of Baby Theresa, Tracy
Latimer, Matthew Donnelly, and Samuel Linares (let alone jellyfish
babies) make a startling contrast with the indifference we show toward
the lives of stray pets, anymals exploited for science and the farming