Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam
![In Search of Consistency: Ethics and Animals [Human–Animal Studies] Part 4 pptx](https://storage.googleapis.com/cloud_leafy_production/1687801008640_1687800999134_277-0.png)
In Search of Consistency: Ethics and Animals [Human–Animal Studies] Part 4 pptx
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
152 chapter four
moral duty to respect the hunted animal” (P. Taylor, Unpublished 2).
(“Inherent worth” is also discussed in chapters 1 and 2.)
Taylor ascribes inherent worth to each entity that has “a good of
their own,” to all those myriad entities that “can be made better or
worse off ” (Respect 56, 75). For Taylor, having a good of one’s own
makes an entity worthy of moral consideration, and moral consideration carries duties for moral agents (Respect 75). If an entity has
inherent worth, then that being is worthy of moral consideration
from moral agents. For Taylor, inherent worth indicates that moral
agents have a prima facie duty to promote or preserve that entity’s
good as an end in itself—for the sake of that entity (Respect 75).
b. Teleology
Taylor’s theory ascribes inherent worth to wild teleological entities.
“Everything that is alive at this moment is the result of ancestors
who displayed brilliant artifices to reproduce against nearly impossible odds” (Sagoff 15). While Western humans have excellent odds
of finding enough food and avoiding predators, this is not the case
for all creatures. Biological beings have a variety of needs; survival
depends on how well they cope with their environment (Broom 90).
In its simplest definition, teleology guides organisms to fulfill biological needs so that they/we might succeed at the daunting task of
survival (G. Williams 136).
Ernest Nagel describes teleology as that which distinguishes “living from inanimate things,” and which specifically refers to “the
apparently purposive character of living organisms” (276). He divides
teleological statements into two types. First are goal ascriptions, which
“state some outcome or goal toward which certain activities of an
organism or of its parts are directed” (E. Nagel 277). For instance,
the goal of pecking in woodpeckers is to find grubs. This form of
teleology is “guided by a program” and “dependent on the existence
of some endpoint or goal” (Mayr 48). Second are function ascriptions, which “make evident one role some item plays in a given system” (E. Nagel 315). This includes for example, “the heart that is
built to pump the blood through the body, the kidneys that are built
to eliminate the byproducts of protein metabolism, the intestinal tract
that performs digestion and makes nutritional material available to
the body,” and teeth that chew food and send the food down to the
digestive tract (Mayr 49). Characteristic language of teleology includes
function, purpose, goal, and behaviors intended to “bring about” a
certain end (Mayr 39).
paul taylor: bio-protectionism 153
Ernst Mayr discusses two other forms of teleology that apply to
inanimate matter. First is a process “in which a definite end is reached
strictly as a consequence of physical laws” (49). Gravity carries a
baseball to the earth as dependably as it carries water to the seas.
Laws of gravitation and thermodynamics frequently govern the unfolding of events on planet earth. “The entire process of cosmic evolution, from the first big bang to the present time” is a direct result
of physical laws such as these (Mayr 49).
Finally, Mayr discusses a cosmic teleology, a form of teleology that
Aristotle attributed to the cosmos as a whole. He did not understand evolution, yet as he studied life and the world around him he
concluded that chance was not a viable explanation for what he witnessed. The world, he thought, must be guided by purpose. Christians
seized on this Aristotelian concept, attributing the ultimate purpose
to God. Mayr notes that this cosmic teleology is rejected by modern science “without reservation. There is not and never was any
program on the basis of which either cosmic or biological evolution
has occurred” (50). Cosmic teleology is now understood to be the
result of “selection forces generated by competition among individuals and species and by the colonization of new adaptive zones”
(Mayr 50).
Taylor’s teleology, consistent with thoughts of most other contemporary thinkers, does not include inanimate forces. Taylor’s moral
theory protects “any wild creature just in virtue of its being a member of a biotic community of a natural ecosystem” (Respect 79). Such
teleological beings are not to be treated as a means to an end, but
as ends in themselves with a value independent of any utility ascribed
by human beings (Respect 57). While “animals may not actually be
valued by humans as highly as other humans [are valued]... this
does not mean that animals do not have the same inherent [worth]
as humans” (“Inherent” 17). In Taylor’s view the spotted sandpiper
and the spotted hyena, the spider wasp and the spider crab all have
inherent worth.
For Taylor, teleology entails both internal functioning and external activities, both of which constantly work to maintain an organism’s existence (Respect 121). Teleological entities have “interests”
because they have a good that can be thwarted: “We have each a
good of our own, and each of us, human and non-human alike, can
be helped or hindered in the realization of that good” (P. Taylor,
“In Defense” 238). Like human beings,
154 chapter four
other organisms are teleological centers of life. The constant tendency
of their behavior and internal processes is patterned around the realization of their good. Although the content of our good and the means
by which we pursue it may be vastly different from theirs, the teleological order exemplified both in our lives and in theirs signifies a fundamental reality common to all of us. (P. Taylor, Respect 157)
Teleological entities pursue the realization of their interests, and
Taylor asserts that to harm the good of a teleological entity thwarts
interests and denies inherent worth (P. Taylor, Respect 71–72). Each
living thing endeavors to maintain its existence. In this ongoing struggle for survival, the unique capacities of each teleological being justify “the ascription of inherent worth to life in general” (“Inherent”
259–60). The essence of goal and function ascriptions—the essence
of teleology—is survival. “The only thing that anything in nature is
designed to accomplish is its own success” (G. Williams 156). Teleological entities strive to persist genetically.
c. Equal Moral Consideration
Entities that have inherent worth are all equally deserving of moral
consideration (P. Taylor, Respect 79). Anymals that have a good of
their own, from the rhinoceros auklet to the elephant shrew, have
moral standing. This moral standing carries corresponding duties for
moral agents.
Taylor asserts that because of teleology, because organisms “grow,
respond to stimuli, reproduce, resist dying, assimilate, and use materials
from their environment” in order to survive, we ought to respect their
efforts and their lives (Scoville 121). There is a measure of equality
in biological beings—all have adapted successfully and are able to
survive in their particular environment (Gunn, “Traditional” 151). Taylor
acknowledges this equality, and this remarkable endeavor that we are
all engaged in, and requires human beings to regard “every entity
which has a good of its own as possessing inherent worth—the same
inherent worth, since none is superior to another” (Respect 155).
4. Moral Agents and Moral Patients
In Taylor’s work, as in Regan’s, moral agents can be held morally
accountable. In contrast, moral patients are not morally accountable;
they cannot do right, nor can they do wrong. Also as in Regan’s
Rights View, Taylor considers most humans to be moral agents,
while anymals (and some humans) are moral patients—though he
paul taylor: bio-protectionism 155
admits he cannot be certain about the moral status of anymals (Respect
14). Taylor’s definition of a moral agent includes
the ability to form judgments about right and wrong; the ability to
engage in moral deliberation, that is to consider and weigh moral reasons for and against various courses of conduct open to choice; the
ability to make decisions on the basis of those reasons; the ability to
exercise the necessary resolve and willpower to carry out those decisions; and the capacity to hold oneself answerable to others for failing to carry them out. (Respect 14)
5. Rights
Taylor introduces and discusses various types of rights in his theory
of Respect for Nature.
a. Legal Rights
Taylor notes that nonhuman entities have legal rights in the Western
world. He defines legal rights as entitlements established by law. He
cites the Endangered Species Act and also laws that prohibit recreational killing of “game” anymals in certain places at certain times,
as proof that both plants and anymals have legal rights (Respect 223).
He notes that legal rights are distinct from moral rights.
b. Moral Rights
Taylor does not ascribe moral rights to anymals. He argues that
moral rights, in contrast to legal rights, can only be ascribed to “persons.” For Taylor, a “person” is an entity that has interests and purposes, preferences and plans, a sense of personal identity over time,
and makes autonomous choices or valuations (Respect 33–36). Additionally, “persons” have self-respect, can exercise or enjoy rights, and
hold others to account (Respect 246, 251). Taylor also asserts that
“persons” are autonomous, rational beings who choose their own
value system and direct their own lives on the basis of their value
system (P. Taylor, Respect 36). Taylor does not find that anymals (or
plants) fulfill the necessary set of criteria for “personhood,” and so
he grants only human beings this status, a status that, in Taylor’s
view, carries moral rights.
In Taylor’s theory, bearers of moral rights “are acknowledged to
have supreme authority over those conditions of their lives which are
essential to preserving their personhood” (“Inherent” 26). Furthermore,
for Taylor, moral rights require that one be a member of a community
156 chapter four
of moral agents. Anymals do not have such supreme authority in
Taylor’s view; he does not recognize them as “persons,” or as bearers of moral rights.
c. Human Rights
Taylor describes human rights as rooted in “human ethics based on
respect for persons.” Taylor views human rights as central to the
structure and function of societies (Respect 234). “The principle of
respect for persons is built into the very structure of the moral community and serves as the ultimate ground of the rules of duty within
the domain of human ethics... [and] serves as the foundation for
universal human rights” (P. Taylor, Respect 39).
Taylor writes that human rights belong “to all persons in virtue
of their personhood. . . . Thus they are universal (belonging to every
person) and equal (the same for all persons)” (“Inherent” 25). Basic
human rights
consist in a set of guaranteed opportunities and permissions which
make it possible for one to (choose to) maintain oneself as a living
organism and to seek those ends of interest that make up the central
values of one’s self-determined conception of a meaningful life. Thus
our basic rights set boundaries of inviolability, as it were, around the
core of our existence. (“Inherent” 25)
Taylor lists several human rights:
• Physical security: the right to subsistence and security, including
the “physical necessities of biological survival,” the right not to be
killed, and the right of physical safety (Respect 235).
• Liberty: the right to liberty entails “freedom from positive external
constraints upon the pursuit of one’s permissible interests” (Respect
237). “Permissible” means those interests that do not infringe on
the rights of others, or break a valid moral rule, including “the right
to take effective steps to realize the goals we have set for ourselves,
without hindrances or obstacles placed in our way by others”; we
are “at liberty to pursue our good as we see fit,” but not necessarily
to have our good realized (Respect 237–39).
• Autonomy: the right to autonomy includes the right to self-determination, which allows individuals to lead their own lives, “based
on goals they set for themselves and values they have chosen for
themselves. . . . [T]hey are accordingly self-directed and self-governed beings” (Respect 239).