Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam
![In Search of Consistency: Ethics and Animals [Human–Animal Studies] Part 2 pot](https://storage.googleapis.com/cloud_leafy_production/1687801007021_1687800997474_300-0.png)
In Search of Consistency: Ethics and Animals [Human–Animal Studies] Part 2 pot
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
40 chapter one
a particular case is engaged to be married to a man who is on trial
for theft, justice is at risk. Vested interests, emotional attachment,
and close affinity threaten impartiality. When one is in charge of
making decisions that affect others, an emotional attachment to only
one (or a portion) of those affected puts justice at risk. This is not to
suggest that emotional attachment or close affinity are vices—rather,
they are virtues. In contrast, complete emotional detachment is a
vice, as evidenced by psychopaths, who are a danger to animals
(including humans). Emotional attachment need not cause bias in all
situations, though such an effect is highly likely.
Human beings, who create moral guidelines for human interactions
with anymals, have vested interests, including an emotional attachment to themselves and to others of their kind. Human beings have
a particular relationship with the human species over and against all
other species, and are likely to have a vested interest in human life.
It is not possible for Homo sapiens to move outside of this position of
bias—it is inherent. However, in the interest of promoting justice,
we must strive to be impartial in spite of our vested interests and
personal connections. Since we are inherently biased, we must be
wary of human assessments of other species, especially assessments
that elevate our own ethical standing. We must critically examine
the means we use to reach conclusions and regard moral assessments
that favor humans as inherently suspicious.
There are scores of examples of biased assessments of other species.
Our first attempt to teach chimpanzees to speak is an example.
Scientists concluded that chimps did not have linguistic ability, that
they lacked the cognitive mechanisms necessary for all but the most
basic forms of communication. Noted scholars concluded that speech
is the exclusive realm of human beings, a defining characteristic
shared by no other animal—and an important element in assessing
moral status. It has since been discovered that chimps lack the physiology for verbal speech, but communicate effectively—beyond basic
communication—via sign language. We are now finding that anymals, such as whales, apes, dolphins, and vervet monkeys, have complex forms of communication (M. S. Dawkins 23–24, Warren 53).
[Vervet] monkeys are able to pick up subtleties in their grunts that
completely escape the human ear. To a human, a grunt is a grunt is
a grunt. It takes technological aids in the form of tape recorders and
sound spectrograph to show that, as far as the monkeys are concerned,
methods and terms 41
there is far more to it than that. . . . We still do not fully understand
what it is that the monkeys are responding to or exactly how they
manage to detect the differences between the grunts. But do it they
clearly do, and they leave their human observers slightly baffled.
(M. S. Dawkins 23–24)
Human investigations into anymal language appear to have carried
an unspoken motive: “For a variety of economic, religious, or other
ideological reasons, it has been important to many people to insist
on an unbridgeable gulf between humans and animals, and language
has seemed the most promising instrument for achieving this” (Dupre
331). Few contemporary ethicists consider language a necessary condition for moral standing; such an assessment is now broadly recognized as a form of humanocentrism (Orlans 150).
Similar to human investigations into language, human understandings
of pain, intelligence, communication, thought, community, learning
ability, and ethics necessarily stem from a narrow perspective, one
gained from an inner understanding of these attributes as parts of our
lives. Rene Descartes (1596–1650) is perhaps the best-known example
of a human being incapable of fairly assessing anymals. He concluded
that other species could neither think nor feel (Descartes 115). Sadly,
while Descartes is a particularly flagrant example, he has not proven
to be an exception to the rule: humans have concocted a plethora
of tests to assess the intelligence, ethical tendencies, and sensitivities
of anymals, with the hope and expectation of further exemplifying
the special and preferable nature of human beings. Ongoing “scientific”
assessments of anymals say more about the nature of science—and
about human nature—than they do about anymals.
Valuing one species over another is not consistent with scientific
information. Darwin provides no hierarchy in the evolutionary continuum, no progression toward perfection, yet even in this “scientific”
age, long after Darwin’s discoveries, people continue to believe that
human beings are the most “advanced.” Concurrently, we believe
that we are the most worthy of moral consideration. But why should
we believe that we are radically different from anymals? All animals
exhibit adaptive behavior and have similar central nervous systems—
we are all sentient. Animals, both Scandinavians and cocker spaniels,
exhibit emotional responses and associate with one another in closeknit groups. If anymals fall short of our expectation, then we should
avow that people do, too.
42 chapter one
[A]ny reason we have to doubt the existence of the minds of animals
also gives us reason to doubt the existence of the minds of other
humans. We are faced with a choice between attributing mental states
to animals and solipsism or skepticism concerning other minds generally. As most of us are quite ready to accept that other human beings
have minds, then we should accept that animals too have minds.
The brains of all multicellular animals, including human beings, are
made of the same matter. The fundamental characteristics of neurons
and synapses are roughly the same. . . . [T]he brains of small whales,
dolphins and porpoises are close in size to those of human beings, both
absolutely and in relation to size of body.
. . . the general truth that animal brains are anatomically similar
to our own must be accepted. And this gives us reason for believing that the mental events that take place ‘within’ them are in some
degree similar to those which occur in our own brains. (Crisp, “Evolution”
310–12)
More specifically, Dawkins argues that “we now know that these
three attributes—complexity, thinking and minding about the world—
are also present in other species. The conclusion that they, too, are
consciously aware is therefore compelling” (M. S. Dawkins 177).
Contemporary science reveals that human beings are not distinct
from anymals in any morally relevant way, leading to the important
and inescapable conclusion that “behavioral and emotional kinship
with nonhuman animals” indicates “moral kinship as well” (Bekoff 360).
Methods of assessing cognition and cognitive abilities lack dependability even among human beings. It is difficult to grasp how people
might come to understand the diverse abilities and interests, psychological tendencies, and mental capabilities of even one other human.
How much more difficult, then, is it for them to understand and
appreciate the minds and feelings of anymals? The epistemological
difficulties inherent in human assessments of anymals must remain
at the center of any discussion of other species and ought to temper any conclusions we reach. Because we have proven partial, and
because we remain inherently partial to our own species, human
studies of anymals cannot reasonably be assumed to be adequately
grounded to justify moral conclusions.
The force and prevalence of speciesism among humans is foreshadowed by the history of human partiality across the categories of
race, sex, age, and sexual orientation. The assumption that all human
beings have moral standing is a recent development. Romans “did
not include in their moral community criminals, captives, foreigners,
or nonhumans” (Marshal 80). When Europeans arrived in North
methods and terms 43
America, they destroyed most of the inhabitants. Only recently has
the United States legally granted African Americans equal moral
consideration. Around the world, women have been (and are) denied
equal moral consideration alongside men. In light of a demonstrated
human tendency for those in power to be partial and unjust in assessing the moral standing of other human beings (particularly when the
assessor has a vested interest), disparaging assessments of anymals is
not surprising.
Another example of human partiality and hubris relates directly
to ethics. Humans have long assumed that only the human animal
has a system of ethics. In spite of modern science and the similarities
that we now know to exist among species, many still assume, without
reference to empirical evidence, that only human beings are ethical
animals. Since ethics is the subject of this book, we should consider
whether or not ethics is exclusively the domain of human beings, or
whether it is a more broad and biological phenomenon of the animal
world (including humans).
A minimal definition of ethics entails a system of behavioral norms
that generate expectations of behavior and punish deviance. Anymals
appear to comply with social expectations and to suffer social punishments for infringements. For instance, the vampire bat displays “animal decision-making... what looks like a system of morality based
on the principle of reciprocation of favours given in the past, coupled with sanctions against those that do not live up to their obligations” (M. S. Dawkins 57). Based on observations, the same might
be true of nonhuman primates, canines, equines, felines, insects, and
perhaps a host of lesser observed anymals (“Inside”).
In the likely event that ethical systems are not exclusively human,
two interesting possibilities arise:
• Ethics, including human ethics, might be genetically encoded.
• Human ethics are but one of many ethical systems in the animal
world.
If the first point is true, then what is esteemed as human ethics may
be merely biology in action. E. O. Wilson argues that “moral sentiments” might be better described as “moral instincts.” If we are to
understand “deep springs of ethical behavior,” he argues that we
must consider the “development of moral sentiments as products of
the interactions of genes and the environment” (64). This argument
makes moral behavior a genetic predisposition resulting from natural
44 chapter one
selection, rather than a metaphysical truth to be discovered (E. O.
Wilson 58–59). E. O. Wilson concludes that ethics are “far more a
product of autonomous evolution than has hitherto been conceded”
(70). While it might prove difficult to explain all of human ethics
through biological analysis, Wilson’s perspective heightens awareness
of human beings as animals, not so very different from anymals. If
ethics have a biological component, it would not be surprising that
our morality is partial, favoring us and our own.
Evolution suggests that if human beings are moral animals by nature,
as has been supposed, other species are also likely to be genetically
wired with an ethical code, or with a tendency to have moral standards
that permit groups of individuals to function and prosper in communities. If this is the case, if other species have and practice their own
forms of morality, philosophers working in ethics have a much broader
field to explore than has generally been assumed. Human morality is
specifically the endeavor of human beings, but since anymals are also
ethical agents in their communities, it is important that we strive to
move outside of our narrow, human perspective of ethics to comprehend a larger moral sphere. Like the judge with a vested interest,
we cannot maintain impartiality, or adequately assess ethical principles
and ethical theories, unless we are able to envisage morality from
something of an “outsider’s” viewpoint. (This does not indicate that
other animals, as moral agents in their own communities, are responsible for righting the wrongs that human beings cause. We are the
animals causing untold suffering and death to other species. We are
the animals who have an ethic that speaks of the importance of consistency and fail to deliver. We need to critically examine our morality
and how we behave, and then change our actions to coincide with
ideals like consistency, justice, and compassion.)
Do genetically encoded morals justify speciesism? History suggests
that morality changes over time, and this may be related to evolution. Our ongoing effort to foster a more inclusive morality indicates
that partiality need not be a permanent part of our genetic code for
moral behavior. If it were, then racism, sexism, ageism, and heterosexism would be equally biological, and we could not expect to
make any moral progress toward a more impartial ethic. History
reveals that this is not the case.
Inherent difficulties, epistemological and personal, indicate that
sound ethical theories are not likely to stem from common human
assumptions or standard human comparisons of themselves with any-