Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam
![In Search of Consistency: Ethics and Animals [Human–Animal Studies] Part 5 pptx](https://storage.googleapis.com/cloud_leafy_production/1687801007811_1687800997938_900-0.png)
In Search of Consistency: Ethics and Animals [Human–Animal Studies] Part 5 pptx
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
208 chapter four
Taylor’s position is inconsistent. He insists that rights are not
“derived from or... equivalent to assertions about duties” because
in such a case “the question of whether moral agents respect the
rights of others becomes identical with the question of whether they
live up to their duties” (“Inherent” 24). Rights, he insists, are more
than this. Given Taylor’s direct parallels, how can he logically assert
that his environmental ethic can supplant anymal and plant rights,
while denying their efficacy as a replacement for human rights?
Taylor’s theory demonstrates that respect for nature is not a replacement for moral rights. Taylor begins chapter six: “In this final chapter I consider the moral dilemmas that arise when human rights and
values conflict with the good of non-humans” (Respect 256). Can the
simple “good” of all other entities compete fairly with the multitude
of comprehensive “rights” Taylor protects for human animals? Taylor’s
theory demonstrates that it cannot. There is bound to be “tension
between claiming that all living beings have equal inherent worth
and only granting rights to humans” (Lombardi 257). Indeed, most
of the difficulties of internal conflict in Taylor’s theory stem from
his tendency to favor human beings, most prominently displayed in
his affirmation of human rights and concurrent dismissal of anymal
rights. Taylor “cannot bring himself to completely renounce... special respect for persons and sometimes speaks of ‘both systems of
ethics’—respect for persons and respect for nature—as if he were
juggling two independent principles” (Callicott, “Case” 107).
Taylor’s acceptance of rights exclusively for Homo sapiens harms
the internal consistency and protectionist qualities of his theory. Most
flagrantly, Taylor offers an environmental ethic to protect “wild”
entities, inclusive of the most civilized and “unnatural” of species
(humans), yet excluding billions of domestic “pets,” “laboratory” anymals, and “food” anymals that live severely truncated, deprived, and
often painful lives. Taylor’s theory allows masses of teleological entities to live and die as property and profit for exploitative industries
that degrade the land with a multitude of chemicals and tons of
waste. Yet Taylor protects these industries, rather than the lives of
the individuals or the environment, allowing people to maintain their
integrity as the type of beings that we are—in this case, greedy,
exploitative, and cruel beings.
Taylor fails to fulfill his own standards for an ethical system; his
humanocentric tendencies prevent him from applying his environmental principles in a disinterested fashion.
paul taylor: bio-protectionism 209
i. Justification
Taylor’s work favors humans in ways that sometimes lead to philosophic inconsistencies, and one might suspect that these special human
privileges are intended to make his theory more palatable: Taylor
guarantees
that we human beings... can go on living the lives to which we have
grown accustomed. He tries to make things come out right—so that
we can eat vegetables, build wooden houses, and generally get on with
our human projects . . .—by means of an elaborate set of hedges enabling
us consumptively to use our fellow entities within the limits of his
extremely broad egalitarian theory. (Callicott, “Case” 108)
Taylor offers a theory that is more likely to be considered acceptable by granting people more freedom and power. Though Taylor
admits that his theory is difficult to realize, he asserts that respect
for nature, based on “equal inherent worth of every living thing,”
demonstrates that “biotic egalitarianism . . . does not reduce to absurdity” but can be fruitfully implemented (Respect 306).
There is value in presenting a moral theory that is appealing and
applicable, one that seems to offer realistic answers to pressing contemporary problems. Yet Taylor’s human leanings prove disastrous,
and in any case, one cannot please everyone. At least one of Taylor’s
readers concluded that “the clearest and most decisive refutation of
the principle of respect for life is that one cannot live according to
it, nor is there any indication in nature that we were intended to”
(Goodpaster, “On Being” 324). Even with Taylor’s extensive human
bias, it is almost certain that many people would be unwilling to
adopt Taylor’s theory of Respect for Nature (Spitler 256).
Moral theory, including protectionist moral theory, ought not to
bend to the preferences of the masses. People have too often treasured
the freedom of human expansion, flourishing civilization, and increased
profit at the expense of other living entities—even at the expense of
less powerful human beings. In the United States, in the mid-eighteenth
century, settlers were free to hunt Native Americans for sport and
profit; those who brought in the head of a Native American were
paid bounty money by the federal government (“Ishi”). In the southern United States slave owners were free to profit economically from
slaves, whom they could sell or kill at their whim. Our interest in
freedom and personal gain has sometimes had an appalling effect
on other individuals—human and nonhuman. Power and freedom
210 chapter four
are much sought, but they are often not worth the price paid (Feinberg, Social 7).
Just as moral theory was brought to bear on those who exploited
Africans and natives for profit in the United States, sound and consistent moral theory must be brought to bear on those who profit
from destroying the natural world or from the lives of anymals.
Conclusion
Taylor’s theory is both broader than most protectionist theories
(including plants) and narrower (excluding anymals that are not “natural” or “wild”). Taylor’s work entails theoretical problems and inconsistencies, such as his tendency to make exceptions in his theory for
the sake of human interests. Nonetheless, Taylor’s theory of Respect
for Nature offers a fascinating and inspirational protectionist ethic
for wildlife, and for the natural world. He offers a much-needed theoretical bridge where environmentalists and protectionists might meet
on common ground.
PART THREE
PROTECTIONIST THEOLOGY