Siêu thị PDFTải ngay đi em, trời tối mất

Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến

Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật

© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

The Future Governance of Citizenship Part 5 ppsx
MIỄN PHÍ
Số trang
24
Kích thước
123.2 KB
Định dạng
PDF
Lượt xem
1992

The Future Governance of Citizenship Part 5 ppsx

Nội dung xem thử

Mô tả chi tiết

record’ condition. Concerning the former requirement, the civic registration

model would posit low residence requirements. This owes much to the fact

that residence generates entitlements, owing to the participation of people in a

web of social interactions and the sense of ‘rootedness’ associated with home

ownership, business ownership, employment, participation in civil associa￾tions, family ties and schooling. De facto social membership and partial de jure

membership in the social and civil spheres make resident non-nationals stake￾holders in the running and the future of the community, thereby strengthening

their claims for political inclusion. Such claims cannot be successfully resisted

by appeals to democracy. Democracy requires inclusion (Dahl 1989) and equal

participation of all those affected by governmental policies in processes of

policy formulation and implementation. This translates into low residence

requirements, ranging from two to three years.45

It may be objected here that one should not become a citizen by simply

inhabiting a place (Miller 1998; Schnapper 1997). After all, communities are

bound together by a shared set of norms, values and cultural practices that give

meaning to individual life projects. Residents must share these commitments,

if they wish to become citizens. From a communitarian perspective, too, only

prolonged residence can provide sufficient guarantees that an individual shares

the national identity of the polity. Such arguments reveal the extent to which

democracy has been configured by nationality in so far as they are underpinned

by the assumption that democracy needs ‘nationals’ more than it needs

democrats, that is, participants in democratic self-government. According to

Van Gustern (1988), the only condition for democratic function is that there is

a willingness to live according to democratic rules and regulations. Nino

(1996) has also stated that ‘the polity should include as full citizens all those

whose interests are at stake in conflict and may be affected by the solution

adopted through the democratic process’. Accordingly, democracy suffers if

there is a divergence between formal citizenship and informal membership

which results in long periods of residence and citizenship without suffrage.

Similarly, it is a deficit of democracy if majoritarianism becomes a vehicle for

the domination of minority groups by a cultural majority and for hardening

existing lines of privilege.

As regards the second requirement of absence of criminal record, one may

observe that this exists in most, if not all, naturalisation laws. In many

countries, absence of criminal record serves to show that the aspiring citizen

45 It is noteworthy here that the Act of 26 March 1790 provided for two years’ residence in the US

for the naturalisation of a free white person. Subsequent acts raised the length of residence to

five and 14 years respectively; Acts of 29 January 1795 and 18 June 1798. In addition, Art. 39,

para. 3, of the Bolivian Constitution of 23 November 1945 (as amended on 20 September 1947

and 26 November 1947) required two years’ residence for the acquisition of Bolivian nation￾ality: ‘The required period of residence is reduced to one year with regard to a person who has a

Bolivian spouse or children or immovable property, or operates a railway or transport under￾taking, or is a school teacher, or is an immigrant under government contract.’

87 Shades of togetherness, patriotism and naturalisation

has a good moral character. In Australia and France, however, absence of

criminal record and good character represent distinctive requirements.

Arguably, the requirement of ‘good character’ is an abstract and vague concept,

and, as such, it can be interpreted in many ways. Historically, the test of ‘good

character’ succeeded religious tests in naturalisation laws. The British natural￾isation laws of 1740 and 1761 contained religious tests and the 1740 law, in

particular, prohibited the naturalisation of Catholics. The first US natural￾isation law of 1790 replaced the religious test with a test of good character as a

prerequisite for US citizenship.46 In Portugal, naturalisation applicants must

be ‘morally and civilly fit’, whereas in Sweden they must lead a respectable life

manifested in the payment of taxes and maintenance.

Although the requirement of ‘absence of criminal record’ is less indetermi￾nate than the ‘good character’ test, much depends on how strictly it is inter￾preted.47 In Austria, for instance, naturalisation is declined if an applicant has

had a prison sentence of three months. Whereas relatively minor offences and

past convictions can by used to exclude people from citizenship under the

republican and communitarian models, under the civic registration approach

an applicant would be refused citizenship if (s)he represented a genuine and

sufficiently serious threat to the requirements of public policy. Previous

criminal convictions would constitute grounds for refusal only in so far as

they indicated clearly a propensity to re-offend or represented punishment for

abhorrent offences, including war crimes and participation in organisations

carrying out violations of human rights. In other words, the crucial consid￾eration would be whether an aspiring citizen constitutes an actual and serious

threat to the interests of the community.

Settlers meeting the requirements of residency and of absence of serious

criminal convictions would thus be entitled to citizenship under the civic

registration model. Naturalisation could be either optional or mixed, that is,

optional after two years of residence and automatic after five years of residence.

Those wishing to opt out from automatic citizenship could always repudiate it

via a declaration.48 It is certainly the case that the civic registration approach

would require the reflexive transformation of existing national conceptions of

group membership and a postconventional understanding of citizenship in

contemporary plural and globalised states. But it would also make democratic

theory ‘go postnational’. The subsequent discussion will substantiate this by

considering possible objections to my argument.

46 Ueda (1980). 47 See, for example, the Anti-Terrorism and Effective Death Penalty Act of 1996, 18 U.S.C. para. 1

et seq. and the Illegal Immigration Reform and Immigrant Responsibility Act, Pub. L. No.

104–208, 110 Stat. 3009–546 (1984) adopted by the American Congress in 1996. 48 In the 1980s in France in the wake of restictionist immigration measures, the argument that

automatic citizenship would deprive second generation migrants of their consent was used in

order to reform the law and to make the acquisition of citizenship by second generation

migrants conditional upon a formal declaration of their wish to become French: Shor (1996).

The nationality reform materialised in 1993.

88 The Future Governance of Citizenship

Tải ngay đi em, còn do dự, trời tối mất!