Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

The Future Governance of Citizenship Part 5 ppsx
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
record’ condition. Concerning the former requirement, the civic registration
model would posit low residence requirements. This owes much to the fact
that residence generates entitlements, owing to the participation of people in a
web of social interactions and the sense of ‘rootedness’ associated with home
ownership, business ownership, employment, participation in civil associations, family ties and schooling. De facto social membership and partial de jure
membership in the social and civil spheres make resident non-nationals stakeholders in the running and the future of the community, thereby strengthening
their claims for political inclusion. Such claims cannot be successfully resisted
by appeals to democracy. Democracy requires inclusion (Dahl 1989) and equal
participation of all those affected by governmental policies in processes of
policy formulation and implementation. This translates into low residence
requirements, ranging from two to three years.45
It may be objected here that one should not become a citizen by simply
inhabiting a place (Miller 1998; Schnapper 1997). After all, communities are
bound together by a shared set of norms, values and cultural practices that give
meaning to individual life projects. Residents must share these commitments,
if they wish to become citizens. From a communitarian perspective, too, only
prolonged residence can provide sufficient guarantees that an individual shares
the national identity of the polity. Such arguments reveal the extent to which
democracy has been configured by nationality in so far as they are underpinned
by the assumption that democracy needs ‘nationals’ more than it needs
democrats, that is, participants in democratic self-government. According to
Van Gustern (1988), the only condition for democratic function is that there is
a willingness to live according to democratic rules and regulations. Nino
(1996) has also stated that ‘the polity should include as full citizens all those
whose interests are at stake in conflict and may be affected by the solution
adopted through the democratic process’. Accordingly, democracy suffers if
there is a divergence between formal citizenship and informal membership
which results in long periods of residence and citizenship without suffrage.
Similarly, it is a deficit of democracy if majoritarianism becomes a vehicle for
the domination of minority groups by a cultural majority and for hardening
existing lines of privilege.
As regards the second requirement of absence of criminal record, one may
observe that this exists in most, if not all, naturalisation laws. In many
countries, absence of criminal record serves to show that the aspiring citizen
45 It is noteworthy here that the Act of 26 March 1790 provided for two years’ residence in the US
for the naturalisation of a free white person. Subsequent acts raised the length of residence to
five and 14 years respectively; Acts of 29 January 1795 and 18 June 1798. In addition, Art. 39,
para. 3, of the Bolivian Constitution of 23 November 1945 (as amended on 20 September 1947
and 26 November 1947) required two years’ residence for the acquisition of Bolivian nationality: ‘The required period of residence is reduced to one year with regard to a person who has a
Bolivian spouse or children or immovable property, or operates a railway or transport undertaking, or is a school teacher, or is an immigrant under government contract.’
87 Shades of togetherness, patriotism and naturalisation
has a good moral character. In Australia and France, however, absence of
criminal record and good character represent distinctive requirements.
Arguably, the requirement of ‘good character’ is an abstract and vague concept,
and, as such, it can be interpreted in many ways. Historically, the test of ‘good
character’ succeeded religious tests in naturalisation laws. The British naturalisation laws of 1740 and 1761 contained religious tests and the 1740 law, in
particular, prohibited the naturalisation of Catholics. The first US naturalisation law of 1790 replaced the religious test with a test of good character as a
prerequisite for US citizenship.46 In Portugal, naturalisation applicants must
be ‘morally and civilly fit’, whereas in Sweden they must lead a respectable life
manifested in the payment of taxes and maintenance.
Although the requirement of ‘absence of criminal record’ is less indeterminate than the ‘good character’ test, much depends on how strictly it is interpreted.47 In Austria, for instance, naturalisation is declined if an applicant has
had a prison sentence of three months. Whereas relatively minor offences and
past convictions can by used to exclude people from citizenship under the
republican and communitarian models, under the civic registration approach
an applicant would be refused citizenship if (s)he represented a genuine and
sufficiently serious threat to the requirements of public policy. Previous
criminal convictions would constitute grounds for refusal only in so far as
they indicated clearly a propensity to re-offend or represented punishment for
abhorrent offences, including war crimes and participation in organisations
carrying out violations of human rights. In other words, the crucial consideration would be whether an aspiring citizen constitutes an actual and serious
threat to the interests of the community.
Settlers meeting the requirements of residency and of absence of serious
criminal convictions would thus be entitled to citizenship under the civic
registration model. Naturalisation could be either optional or mixed, that is,
optional after two years of residence and automatic after five years of residence.
Those wishing to opt out from automatic citizenship could always repudiate it
via a declaration.48 It is certainly the case that the civic registration approach
would require the reflexive transformation of existing national conceptions of
group membership and a postconventional understanding of citizenship in
contemporary plural and globalised states. But it would also make democratic
theory ‘go postnational’. The subsequent discussion will substantiate this by
considering possible objections to my argument.
46 Ueda (1980). 47 See, for example, the Anti-Terrorism and Effective Death Penalty Act of 1996, 18 U.S.C. para. 1
et seq. and the Illegal Immigration Reform and Immigrant Responsibility Act, Pub. L. No.
104–208, 110 Stat. 3009–546 (1984) adopted by the American Congress in 1996. 48 In the 1980s in France in the wake of restictionist immigration measures, the argument that
automatic citizenship would deprive second generation migrants of their consent was used in
order to reform the law and to make the acquisition of citizenship by second generation
migrants conditional upon a formal declaration of their wish to become French: Shor (1996).
The nationality reform materialised in 1993.
88 The Future Governance of Citizenship