Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

THE HEALTH OF NATIONS Part 5 doc
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
european governance 167
and processes, is that the idea ofcivil society is capable ofproducing
the idea ofthe state, which finally embodies, in theory and in practice, society’s universalising capacity, an achievement which is the rationally conceived end ofhuman history. And, in appropriate historical
circumstances, such as a ‘constitutional monarchy’, the idea ofthe ‘state’
could become a fact. One thing was certain. The surpassing of civil society in the ‘state’ could not be achieved in the form of democracy, if that
meant a system in which the masses (der P¨obel) would, in some sense,
govern.
6.13 The consequences ofHegel’s depreciation of‘civil society’ in
relation to ‘the state’ have been profound and long-lasting. In the hands
ofKarl Marx, misled perhaps by the unfortunate German translation of
Ferguson’s ‘civil society’ as b¨urgerliche Gesellschaft (bourgeois society),18
it became the casus belli ofrevolution, the end ofhumanity’s pre-history.
At the same time, the development ofHegel’s ‘universal class’, in the form
ofthe modern paternalist civil service, with its universalising function
in the service ofthe public interest, rapidly became a feature ofliberal
democracy, even in the most bourgeois ofliberal democracies. But the
contempt for, or at least distrust of, the messy business of democratic
‘politics’, particularly politics ofthe Anglo-American variety, continued
to affect the political development of several European countries until
well into the twentieth century.19 And Hegel’s troubled spirit may be
with us yet again, in the third and latest life-form of ‘civil society’ and
in its conceptual cousin, the sinister new concept of‘governance’.
6.14 It was in the last two decades ofthe twentieth century that the
idea of‘civil society’ was suddenly and mysteriously resurrected or reincarnated. The third life of civil society has already generated its own
book-mountain. There is some agreement to the effect that the idea had
two spiritual parents: a decline ofconfidence in the business ofinstitutional politics in liberal democracies; and a tactic ofanti-state dissent
in late-stage communist countries.20 But there is a splendid range of
disparate views about what ‘civil society’ is and is for. Civil Society 1.
For some, particularly for ever-optimistic Americans, it is the arena for
18 It seems that civil society’s latest avatar has been re-branded in German as Zivilgesellschaft. 19 For further discussion of this aspect, see ch. 7 below, at §§ 7.50ff. 20 The most memorable case ofthis phenomenon was the role oftrade unions in the revolutionary social transformation of Poland, but the idea of ‘anti-politics’ had for some time
been an aspect ofthe polemics ofdissidence in Eastern Europe.
168 european soc iety and its law
the revival ofFergusonian community, civility and republican virtue
as a therapeutic response to institutional corruption.21 Civil Society 2.
For others, apparently including the European Commission, it is a neosyndicalist assertion ofthe countervailing power ofnon-state organised
interests, mediating between the particularism ofthe individual and the
institutional universality ofthe state.22 Civil Society 3. For others again,
it is the embodiment ofa Habermasian public sphere in which the differentiated voices ofsociety speak to each other and collectively constitute
the consciousness oftheir sociality and perhaps even oftheir humanity.23 Civil Society 4. For the apostles ofuniversal democracy, it is the
means by which societies whose social development has been delayed or
disabled can artificially construct the social sub-structure without which
democratic institutions cannot function successfully. And the same principle might be applicable to the democratising ofinternational society
itself.24
6.15 The spiritual connection between such ideas and the idea of
‘governance’ is subtle. The word ‘governance’ in the English language
(derived from the Old French gouvernance) is older than the word ‘government’. It referred to any form of control – of a parent over a child,
a natural force, a king’s power over a kingdom. John Fortescue’s The
Governance of England (written in the 1460s, first printed in 1714) was
21 ‘The idea ofcivil society is the idea ofsociety which has a life ofits own which is separate
from the state, and largely autonomous from it, which lies beyond the boundaries of the
family and the clan, and beyond the locality.’ E. Shils, ‘The virtue of civility’ (revised version
ofan essay originally published in 1991), in E. Shils, The Virtue of Civility. Selected Essays
on Liberalism,Tradition,and Civil Society (Indianapolis, Liberty Fund; 1997), pp. 320–55, at
pp. 320–1. 22 Syndicalism was a movement, especially in pre-fascist Italy, which sought to take power
over (or, in its anarcho-syndicalist version, to replace) the power ofthe state by using the
social power ofcorporate entities (sindacati), especially trade unions. Hegel had approved
ofthe non-governmental collective entity (Korporation) as a means ofpartial universalising
within Hegelian civil society. 23 ‘A viable civil society as a kind ofthird force between the state and the economy, on the
one hand, and the private sphere, on the other, seems to require some effective sense of
community and ofthere actually being a community to which people are committed.’
K. Nielson, ‘Reconceptualizing civil society for now’, in Toward a Global Civil Society (ed.
M. Walzer; Providence, Berghahn Books; 1995), pp. 41–67, at p. 56. 24 Governments and intergovernmental organisations have adopted this idea as an article
offaith. National and international non-governmental organisations have been incidental
beneficiaries to the extent that their claim to be self-appointed and self-defined institutions
ofnational and international ‘civil society’ is recognised by governments and intergovernmental organisations.
european governance 169
the first constitutional treatise written in the English language.25 It was
an instruction manual for a king on the art of wise governance of the
kingdom. In The Governance and also in his better-known De Laudibus
Legum Angliae(In Praise ofthe Laws ofEngland), written for the instruction ofthe then Prince ofWales and first printed in 1537, Fortescue had
explained that the King ofEngland is ‘not only regal but also political’,26
that he has dominium politicum et regale.
27 This meant that the English
polity was to be regarded as a monarchy which was, in some sense, also a
republic.28 The King ‘is not able to change the laws without the assent of
his subjects nor to burden an unwilling people with strange impositions
[taxes]’; ‘for a king of this sort is set up for the protection of the law,
the subjects, and their bodies and goods, and he has power to this end
issuing from the people, so that it is not permissible for him to rule his
people with any other power’.29
6.16 In The Governance Fortescue took up, with remarkable acuity,
what would prove to be one ofthe great perennial themes ofEnglish
constitutional history, a theme which has traditionally been known as
the problem of‘influence behind the throne’,30 a theme which is raised
yet again, six centuries later, by the new ideas of‘civil society’ and ‘governance’ and in a political world full of focus groups, lobbyists, special
interest groups and non-governmental organisations ofdubious representative legitimacy and with purposes which may or may not be for the
common good.
6.17 Fortescue devoted much attention to the problem ofthe composition ofthe King’s Council, the embryo-form ofcabinet government.
25 Sir John Fortescue (c.1394–c.1476) was briefly ChiefJustice ofthe King’s Bench. He went into
exile with the Prince ofWales and his mother (Margaret ofAnjou, wife ofKing Henry VI,
who had been deposed in 1461) but was later reconciled with King Edward IV (reigned
1461–83) and became a member ofhis Council. 26 J. Fortescue, De laudibus legum Angliae, in J. Fortescue, On The Laws and Governance of
England (ed. S. Lockwood; Cambridge, Cambridge University Press; 1997), ch. 1. 27 J. Fortescue, The Governance of England (ed. C. Plummer; Oxford, Clarendon Press; 1885),
ch. 1. 28 Both Voltaire and Montesquieu would come to the same conclusion in their observations
on the English constitution. See further in ch. 7 below, at § 7.31, fn. 30. 29 J. Fortescue, De laudibus (fn. 26 above), chs 9 and 13, pp. 17, 21–2. 30 There is, perhaps, a connection with the German phenomenon, discussed by Weber, of R¨ate
von Haus aus (counsel from beyond the court), a controversial practice of German kings.
M. Weber, ‘Bureaucracy’ (part 3, ch. 6 of Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft), in From Max Weber:
Essays in Sociology (eds H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills; London, Routledge; 1948/1991),
pp. 196–244, at p. 236.
170 european soc iety and its law
The Council must be carefully composed, including some commoners,
and it must be possible to know who is advising the King. In a paper of1470, he referred to the bad practice whereby ‘our kings have
been ruled by private Counsellors, such as have offered their service
and counsel and were not chosen thereto’.31 Four centuries later, John
Stuart Mill raised the problem yet again, borrowing a phrase from Jeremy
Bentham: ‘sinister interests . . . that is, interests conflicting more or less
with the general good ofthe community’. ‘One ofthe greatest dangers,
therefore, ofdemocracy, as ofall other forms ofgovernment, lies in
the sinister interest ofthe holders ofpower.’32 Should we recognise the
fact that there may even be such a thing as ‘the interest of a ruling
class’?33
The lure of anti-politics
6.18 We may, indeed, wonder what it is that attracts the direct successors ofthe medieval kings, the ruling classes ofthe European Union
and ofits member states and ofinternational unsociety, and the ruling
class ofthe capitalist economy, to the new ideas of‘civil society’ and
‘governance’ and to a re-branding ofliberal democracy and capitalism
which is also a dangerous reconceiving ofessential features ofliberal
democracy and capitalism. In whose interest would such a thing be?34
6.19 In Plato’s Protagoras, Protagoras says that Hermes asked Zeus,
no less, whether he should distribute the gifts of wise government only
to the few, as special skills are given to doctors and lawyers and other
experts, or to all alike. Zeus answered: ‘Let all have their share.’35 From
31 J. Fortescue, The Governance (fn. 27 above), pp. 301, 346. 32 J. S. Mill, Considerations on Representative Government (1861) (London, Dent (Everyman’s
Library); 1910), ch. 6, pp. 248, 254. 33 Ibid., p. 249. John Locke said that ifthe Prince had ‘a distinct and separate Interest from
the good ofthe Community’ then the people would not be ‘a Society ofRational Creatures’
but would have to be seen as ‘an Herd ofinferiour Creatures, under the Dominion ofa
Master, who keeps them, and works them for his own Pleasure and Profit’. Two Treatises
on Government (1689) (ed. P. Laslett; Cambridge, Cambridge University Press; 1960), ii,
§ 163, p. 423. 34 Cui bono? (who would profit from it?). Cicero, who used the phrase in the Second Philippic,
attributed it to the judge Lucius Cassius. 35 Plato, Protagoras, 322c–d (tr. W. Guthrie), in The Collected Dialogues of Plato (eds E. Hamilton
and H. Cairns; Princeton, Princeton University Press; 1961), p. 320. Protagoras goes on to
say: ‘Thus it is, Socrates, and from this cause, that in a debate involving skill in building,