Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

THE HEALTH OF NATIONS Part 4 pot
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
the nat ion as m ind pol it ic 121
as things turned out, determined the subsequent course ofEuropean
history, and then ofworld history.
Nation and pathology
4.56 It follows from all that has been said above that the moral problem
ofthe behaviour ofnations in the twentieth century – in particular, the
evil which has been done by nations acting through state-systems and by
nations at odds with state-systems – is a complex one. We have identified
a set ofpowerful resistances which must somehow be overcome ifwe
are to understand and to deal with the problem:
(1) the indeterminacy oftranscendental philosophy undermines our
capacity to understand the phenomena ofthe nation rationally and
to judge them morally;
(2) the naturalism ofthe humane sciences detaches the phenomena of
the nation from our subjectivity, including our moral consciousness,
individual and collective;
(3) the naturalism ofthe humane sciences renders us passive in relation
to the behaviour (political, economic, technological) ofthe nation,
as passive as a remote tribe cowering before the omnipotence of
Nature;
(4) and yet our minds are full of the overflowing subjectivity of the
modern nation, ofour own nation or nations, and ofother nations;
(5) and the institutional authority ofthe state-systems relentlessly appropriates the phenomena ofnational subjectivity and transforms
them into facts ofpower, instruments ofpower, commodities.
4.57 In short, we feel that we cannot judge the nation and its works,
we cannot control the nation and its works, and yet we cannot escape
the nation and its works.
4.58 To oppose such formidable forces, we have been able to summon up only a modest array ofintellectual weapons:
(1) the idea that the mind which is involved in the mind politic ofthe
nation is precisely the same mind as the mind which is involved in
individualised human behaviour;
(2) the idea that self-nationising is the same process as self-personising,
forming a subjective totality which feeds on the mind that it feeds;
122 soc iety and law
(3) the idea that, having regard to (1) and (2), there is an indissoluble
moral unity between the nation as mind politic and the person as
mind individualised.
4.59 So it is that we find ourselves in the same condition – but what a
different condition after three such centuries! – as the self-contemplating
Descartes. The best efforts of philosophy, of academicism, of scientism,
ofeconomism and ofstate-power cannot separate us from that first
hearth and last refuge which is our own consciousness. In our immediate
and inescapable experience ofour internal forum we must find the means
to re-experience the public forum. In the communicating of our own
selfwith itself, our most intimate experience, we must find the means
to communicate with, and to cure, the self-communicating nation.
4.60 How to begin? We could try to re-experience, as ifwe were
reliving some personal experience ofour own, the development ofthe
self-consciousness of actual nations. Using, as compass and map, our
own conceptions ofwhat it is to be a person, what it is to be a healthy
or a virtuous person, what it is to be a diseased or an evil person, we
might begin to imagine a way to find a sympathetic understanding of
self-nationing, the kind of understanding which alone would entitle us
to pass judgement on the behaviour ofnations, and to condemn, ifneed
be, the evil that nations do, and to propose therapies for the sicknesses
that afflict nations and those whom they infect with their sicknesses. To
make a start somewhere, we might consider, as a tentative and rudimentary thought-experiment, what is perhaps the most striking instance of
modern times – the reconceiving ofGerman national consciousness in
the nineteenth century.
4.61 Beginning in the period ofGerman Romanticism, Germans set
themselves the task ofrediscovering not only what it is to be human
(a task that they shared with European Romantics everywhere) but also
what it is to be German. They went in search ofwhat Hegel would call ‘the
indwelling spirit and the history ofthe nation . . . by which constitutions
have been made and are made’.35 It was a task made easier by the relative
35 G. W. F. Hegel, Philosophy of Mind (fn. 27 above), § 540, pp. 268–9. Hegel was disparaging
about the medieval mystifying of Germany’s origins: Avineri, Modern State (fn. 34 above),
p. 229, also at pp. 21–2. Gellner is dismissive, scornful even, of attempts to universalise the
idea ofthe nation, to make ofit a natural and inevitable category ofhuman socialisation.
The idea ofthe nation is a contingent thing, arising in particular ways in particular social
conjunctures. See ‘Nationalism and the two forms of cohesion’, fn. 10 above, passim. ‘The
the nat ion as m ind pol it ic 123
sparseness ofthe information and by the passage oftime, and it was a
task which, for the same reasons, could be, at one and the same time,
an enthralling exercise in dry-as-dust objectivity and a thrilling exercise
in rampant subjectivity. With remarkable facility and with surprising
certainty there could be conjured out ofthe cold northern mists ofa
remote Teutonic past a German selfwhich was heroic and pure and
creative and dynamic and masterful. In such an interesting mirror, it
was possible to see and to judge a German selfthat had somehow, in the
meantime, become petty and and provincial and bloodless and aimless.
It was not difficult to see that Germany was a genetic nation which had
collapsed into a patchwork ofinsignificant nations, together forming
some sort ofshadowy and unsatisfactory generic nation, a nation which
had not remained true to its selfbut which could, perhaps, be made to
become its true selfonce again.
4.62 In the office of official psychoanalysts to the German nation,
the brothers Grimm, whom we may take as symbolic heroes ofa movement which involved countless scholars, including adepts ofthe new
human naturalism, were able by their vast labours to bring up from
the depths ofGerman unconsciousness a German soul which manifested itself uniquely in German language, German folk-tales, German
literature, German art, German religion, and even a German mythology.36 In a more Jungian framework, Richard Wagner (once again, a
hero-figure standing for countless German artists and writers) transmuted the new consciousness through the magical processes ofart into
something which could return, as all art does, to take on a new universalised life in the depths of German unconsciousness.37 By these means,
German consciousness, at its most articulated and at its most secret, was
changed.
4.63 The German case is merely an extraordinarily open and explicit
and purposeful example of what all nations do all the time, in a much
more disordered way. It raises, as all such cases do, the questions ofwhy
such a reforming of national self-consciousness occurs and what are its
consequences.
great, but valid, paradox is this: nations can be defined only in terms ofnationalism, rather
than, as you might expect, the other way round.’ E. Gellner, Nations and Nationalism (Oxford,
Basil Blackwell; 1983), p. 55. 36 J. Grimm, Deutsche Mythologie (1835). 37 R. Wagner, My Life (tr. A. Gray; New York, Da Capo; 1983), pp. 280, 343.
124 soc iety and law
4.64 In the case ofGermany in the nineteenth century, it seems
particularly perverse that a people should redefine themselves in so romantic a spirit when (a) German scholars were using the spirit ofobjectivity to carry the humane sciences and the natural sciences to the
highest levels attained anywhere in Europe; (b) the Prussian state was
leading Europe in the rational reorganisation ofthe social, ifnot ofthe
political, aspects ofsociety; and (c) German business and industry were
applying the lessons ofthe British industrial revolution to generate an
economy which was rapidly overtaking, in scale and sophistication, any
other European economy.
4.65 Renan drew attention to the essential part that forgetting and
error play in the formation of national consciousness.38 The self-image
may be based on false information about the past and present situation ofthe nation, and it may, probably must, involve the repression of
much in that situation which is inconsistent with the ideal-self-image.
We may go further and say that national self-consciousness is a form of
private fantasy, a reality-for-themselves of the nationals whose relationship to the reality-for-non-nationals is secondary. However, in the case
of nations, the private fantasy is necessarily a public fantasy. The development ofGerman consciousness was as much a matter ofinterest for
other Europeans, especially the French and the British, as was German
material progress. Germans were fellow members of a European society,
a European family, a European nation even, and their state of mind could
not be a matter of indifference to the other members. To a greater extent
with the French and to a lesser extent with the unreflective British, the
development ofa new German consciousness generated modifications
in all non-German national consciousness.39
4.66 In these facts lie the roots ofthe pathology ofnational consciousness.
38 ‘Qu’est-ce qu’une nation?’, in E. Renan, Oeuvres compl`etes (Paris, Calmann-Levy; 1947), i,
p. 891. 39 On Franco-German mutual self-nationalising, see Taguieff (fn. 32 above), passim; and
P. Birnbaum, ‘Nationalisme a la franc ` ¸aise’, same volume, pp. 125–38. See also L. Dumont,
L’id´eologie allemande. France-Allemagne et retour (Paris, Gallimard; 1991). Compare Adam
Ferguson: ‘Athens was necessary to Sparta, in the exercise ofher virtue, as steel is to flint
in the production offire.’ An Essay on the History of Civil Society (1767) (ed. D. Forbes;
Edinburgh, Edinburgh University Press; 1966), p. 59. Discussed in P. Gay, The Enlightenment (fn. 10 above), pp. 340ff. For a comparison of British, French and German national
constitutional psychologies, see ch. 7 below.