Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

THE FATAL CONCEIT The Errors of Socialism phần 9 docx
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
APPENDIX B
THE COMPLEXITY OF PROBLEMS OF
HUMAN INTERACTION
Although physical scientists sometimes appear unwilling to recognise
the greater complexity of the problems of human interaction, the fact
itself was seen more than a hundred years ago by no less a figure than
James Clerk Maxwell, who in 1877 wrote that the term `physical
science' is often applied `in a more or less restricted manner to those
branches of science in which the phenomena considered are of the
simplest and most abstract kind, excluding the consideration of the
more complex phenomena such as those observed in living things'. And
more recently a Nobel laureate in physics, Louis W. Alvarez, stressed
that `actually physics is the simplest of all the sciences.... But in the
case of an infinitely more complicated system, such as the population of
a developing country like India, no one can yet decide how best to
change the existing conditions' (Alvarez, 1968).
Mechanical methods and models of simple causal explanation are
increasingly inapplicable as we advance to such complex phenomena.
In particular, the crucial phenomena determining the formation of
many highly complex structures of human interaction, i.e., economic
values or prices, cannot be interpreted by simple causal or 'nomothetic'
theories, but require explanation in terms of the joint effects of a larger
number of distinct elements than we can ever hope individually to
observe or manipulate.
It was only the `marginal revolution' of the 1870s that produced a
satisfactory explanation of the market processes that Adam Smith had
long before described with his metaphor of the `invisible hand', an
account which, despite its still metaphorical and incomplete character,
was the first scientific description of such self-ordering processes. James
and John Stuart Mill, by contrast, were unable to conceive of the
determination of market values in any manner other than causal
determination by a few preceding events, and this inability barred
them, as it does many modern 'physicalists', from understanding selfsteering market processes. An understanding of the truths underlying
marginal utility theory was further delayed by James Mill's guiding
influence on David Ricardo, as well as by Karl Marx's own work.
Attempts to achieve mono-causal explanations in such areas (prolonged
14 8
APPENDIX B
even longer in England through the decisive influence of Alfred
Marshall and his school) persist to the present.
John Stuart Mill perhaps played the most important role in this
connection. He had early put himself under socialist influence, and
through this bias acquired a great appeal to `progressive' intellectuals,
establishing a reputation as the leading liberal and the `Saint of
Rationalism'. Yet he probably led more intellectuals into socialism than
any other single person: fabianism was in its beginnings essentially
formed by a group of his followers.
Mill had barred his way to comprehending the guide function of
prices by his doctrinaire assurance that `there is nothing in the laws of
value which remains for the present or any future writer to clear up'
(1848/1965, Works: III, 456), an assurance that made him believe that
` considerations of value had to do with [the distribution of wealth]
alone' and not with its production (1848/1965, Works, III: 455). Mill
was blinded to the function of prices by his assumption that only a
process of mechanical causation by some few observable preceding
events constituted a legitimate explanation in terms of the standards of
natural science. Due to the influence that Mill's assumption had exerted
for so long, the `marginal revolution' of twenty-five years later, when it
did arrive, had an explosive effect.
It deserves mentioning here, however, that only six years after Mill's
textbook was published, H. H. Gossen, a thinker who is almost wholly
overlooked, had anticipated marginal utility theory in already clearly
recognising the dependence of extended production on guidance by prices
and emphasising that `only with the establishment of private property can
the yardstick be found for the determination of the optimal quantity of each
commodity to be produced under given circumstances.... The greatest
possible protection of private property is definitely the greatest necessity for
the continuation of human society' (1854/1983:254-5).
Despite the great harm done by his work, we must probably forgive
Mill much for his infatuation with the lady who later became his wife -
upon whose death, in his opinion, `this country lost the greatest mind it
contained' and who, according to his testimony, `in the nobleness of her
public object ... never stopped short of perfect distributive justice as
the final aim, implying therefore a state of society entirely communist in
practice and spirit' (1965, Works: XV, 601; and see Hayek, 1951).
Whatever the influence of Mill may be, Marxian economics is still
today attempting to explain highly complex orders of interaction in
terms of single causal effects like mechanical phenomena rather than as
prototypes of those self-ordering processes which give us access to the
1 49