Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

The Ethics and Governance of Human Genetic Databases European Perspectives Part 7 pps
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
the issue of benefit-sharing further. A differentiation is useful between the
universal list above (describing the entire positive potential of the genetic
enterprise) and a specific benefit-sharing framework directed towards
those who directly participate in research.26 These two issues should
not be joined if we still want to make use of the sharing framework,
and by differentiation much confusion is avoided because a number of
benefit-sharing arguments function only in a specific context, whereas
others have relevance universally. For example, compensation for risks
taken is an important aspect where smaller research projects are concerned and desert might be considered a relevant distributive principle.
Alternatively, compensation for fairness and the principles of need and
equality gain significance in cases of successful drug development for
diseases rampant in the poorer areas of the world.
Benefit-sharing and population biobanks
The practice of benefit-sharing, especially as first applied in agriculture,
introduced a perspective that recognizes the contributions of communities and populations. Human genetics complicated the issue further as
genetic information is by nature shared, thus involving individuals and
communities who might not have participated in research in the traditional sense. As research is increasingly associated with for-profit companies and practices, this has given credence to additional concerns of
political, social and economic origin. Of course, in principle ‘genetic
research on a global scale’ is still made up of specific research projects,
but many calls for benefit-sharing ask us to look beyond these specific
projects and assess the impact of the entire phenomenon, inclusive of
factors outside the regulated medical sphere. It is like taking stock of the
ocean instead of focusing on the drops of water making it up.
Population biobanks provide an intersection for benefit-sharing concerns – whilst mostly focused on medical research, they ill-fit the traditional medical frameworks (for example, besides benefit-sharing the
appropriate redefinition(s) of informed consent have been a significant
challenge). The very scale and scope of population biobanks have introduced new concerns for fairness and justice that call for a different
justification for benefit-sharing. But, of course, fairness and various
justice-related concepts are notoriously difficult to agree upon. For instance,
whose concerns are to be taken as relevant? In small-scale research
26 Kadri Simm, ‘Benefit-Sharing: An Inquiry Regarding the Meaning and Limits of
the Concept in Human Genetic Research’, Genomics, Society and Policy 1, 2 (2005),
pp. 29–40.
168 Kadri Simm
projects this is easier to assess than in biobanks, where significant social
concerns might arise.
It is also important to draw attention to the way justifying arguments
for benefit-sharing determine the recipients of those benefits. In other
words, certain justifications necessarily exclude or include specific groups
or communities. For example, when we consider the genome to be a
common property of humanity, the sharing should be done among all
human beings. On the other hand, when benefit-sharing is conceptualized as a compensation for voluntarily taken risks, it would seem unfair
to share benefits with those who have not taken any risks. Furthermore,
different justifications can be contradictory and the employment of those
competing concerns can complicate the issue further.
In biobanks the question will inevitably be raised as regards who
in particular will benefit. Can and should a relevant community be
delineated when not everyone will be involved? The case of individual
benefits (as in the Estonian promise of giving individual feedback based
on DNA samples) could be a strictly desert-based undertaking. The
Icelandic project has promised cheaper drugs based on research results,
but it is unclear whether that would include non-participants. By contrast, the UK Biobank explicitly does not promise personal gains and
insists on the altruistic motivation of the participants: they expect the
participation of the elderly but the expressly stated objective is to benefit
all (also outside the UK), thus making solidarity central in sharing scientific benefits.
It is an open question whether population biobanks would rather
follow the traditional reciprocal form of benefit-sharing or whether
more inclusive arrangements based on solidarity are taken up. The concept of benefit-sharing has been transformed as ethical, social, political,
economic and scientific developments have had their impact on research.
The rationale for benefit-sharing within biobanks can rely on competing
discourses, and it is largely up to the organizers as well as the participants
to decide upon the content of this notion.
Benefit-sharing and biobanks 169
20 Genetic discrimination
Lena Halldenius
The argument in this chapter proceeds from an empirical fact and a
conceptual dissatisfaction. ‘Genetic discrimination’ is now an ethical
and legal issue. In countries like France, Denmark and Norway insurance
companies and employers are banned from asking individuals to undergo
or disclose results from genetic tests. There is backing in the Council of
Europe’s Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine1
and the
Universal Declaration on the Human Genome and Human Rights.2
The term ‘discrimination’ is explicitly used in these documents. In
Sweden, legislation was recently proposed by a parliamentary committee.
The proposals affect both the insurance sector (previously regulated in a
trade agreement) and the employment sector (previously unregulated).3
The genetic discrimination scare is exacerbated by plans to build
population genetic biobanks and databases in several countries, like
Estonia and the UK. In Sweden there is no such comprehensive genetic
project underway, but the PKU register holds blood samples from every
individual born in Sweden since 1975. These large-scale biobanks raise
ethical issues not only about consent procedures, data protection, and
whether people should have a right to know (or not to know) what their
genetic make-up looks like. They also raise issues about the ethical
viability of third-party use. Genetic information is ever becoming more
and more accessible. With the advent of large-scale biobanks and genetic
1
‘Any form of discrimination against a person on grounds of his or her genetic heritage is
prohibited’, Convention on the Protection of Human Rights and Dignity of the Human
Being with Regard to the Application of Biology and Medicine: Convention on Human
Rights and Biomedicine, Oviedo, 4 April 1997, ETS 164, art. 11.
2
‘No one shall be subjected to discrimination based on genetic characteristics that is
intended to infringe or has the effect of infringing human rights, fundamental freedoms
and human dignity’, UNESCO, The Universal Declaration on the Human Genome and
Human Rights, adopted by the General Conference of UNESCO at its 29th Session on
11 November 1997, art. 6.
3
SOU 2004:20 Genetics, Integrity and Ethics, Final Report from the Committee on
Genetic Integrity (SOU 2004:20 Genetik, integritet och etik. Slutbeta¨nkande av
Kommitte´n om genetisk integritet).
170