Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

The Ethics and Governance of Human Genetic Databases European Perspectives Part 2 pptx
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
There are certain decisions which are, so to speak, only ours to make.
Some of them concern our bodies, others the attainment and disclosure
of information about ourselves. These define the domain of our decisional
privacy. Respect for this can imply, for instance, that we have a ‘right to
choose what happens in and to our bodies’, as some people have claimed
in the abortion debate. Decisions concerning personal data are intrinsically related to the informational aspect of our privacy.
Consent
Permission to seek, store and disseminate genetic information about
individuals can be obtained in many ways. The standard approaches in
the biomedical context are based on the notions of ‘actual’, ‘implied’,
‘hypothetical’ and ‘proxy’ consent.
Actual consent is the real, genuine permission of the individuals themselves to collect, store and disseminate their tissue samples or genetic
data. In medical contexts, consent is, as a rule, considered valid only if
three conditions are met. The individual consenting must be competent,
not permanently or temporarily unable to make reasonably clear-headed
decisions for herself. The consent must be given freely, not as a result of
coercion, intimidation or pressure. And the individual must be informed
as to what exactly she consents to, and what the implications of the
decision for her will, or can, be.
Implied consent (also known as ‘presumed consent’) is the notion evoked
in cases where individuals have not actually consented or dissented to the
procedure in question, but others claim that their permission can, nevertheless, be assumed. The claim can be backed up by various strategies.
One is to point out that a genuine opportunity to register dissent has been
given to individuals, but they have chosen not to use it. Another is to
appeal to related evidence which gives indirect support to the assumption, perhaps by showing that the same people have not in the past
dissented to similar practices in other fields.6
Hypothetical consent (or ‘rational consent’) can be used even in cases
where we know nothing about the actual or probable attitudes of the
individuals involved. We can then hypothesize that they are rational or
moral in a sense defined by us, and assert that these qualities necessarily
elicit, or should elicit, certain responses from them. We may think that no
6 On how dangerous it is to read more into what people say than they actually do say, see,
e.g., Søren Holm, ‘ ‘‘Parity of Reasoning Arguments in Bioethics’’ – Some Methodological
Considerations’, in Matti Ha¨yry and Tuija Takala (eds.), Scratching the Surface of Bioethics
(Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2003), pp. 47–56.
18 Matti Ha¨yry and Tuija Takala
rational person would object to having her genetic data stored. Or we may
argue that since individuals have benefited, or will benefit, from other
people’s willingness to participate, they cannot therefore claim a moral
right to opt out.
Proxy consent is introduced in situations where the individuals themselves are temporarily incapacitated, persistently incompetent or dead.
The permission in these cases is not sought from them, but from some
other people, usually their relatives or friends. This form of consent is
resorted to in medical emergencies, in cases where the individuals themselves cannot make reasonably sound decisions, and in dealings with
small children.
Confidentiality
In medical and certain other settings, we can consent to share some
private information with other people or institutions, on the condition that
they do not pass it on to anybody else, or at least not to any unauthorized third parties. In theory, confidentiality can be regarded as an absolute
or a qualified requirement.
Respect for absolute confidentiality would require that the information
acquired will under no circumstances be made public, disseminated or
passed on to any other, or any unauthorized, parties. Ethicists have
sometimes tried to impose this kind of duty on those who receive, in
their professional capacity, sensitive and personal knowledge about their
patients or clients. In practice, however, strict obligations like this are
often difficult to honour.7
Respect for qualified confidentiality requires a presumption of secrecy,
but recognizes the need, in exceptional cases, to breach the confidentiality of individuals, either to uphold other moral principles, or for their own
good, or for the good of others. This is linked with, among other things,
public interest. It has been argued, for instance, that family doctors
should, or should be allowed to, disclose information about potentially
lethal socially transmissible conditions to the family members of their
patients. In the context of genetics, the claim has been made that blood
relatives should be entitled to have access to each other’s genetic records.8
7
See, e.g., Raanan Gillon, Philosophical Medical Ethics (Chichester: John Wiley & Sons,
1985), pp. 108–109.
8
See, e.g., Rosamond Rhodes, ‘Genetic Links, Family Ties and Social Bonds: Rights and
Responsibilities in the Face of Genetic Knowledge’, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy
23 (1998), pp. 10–30. Cf., however, Tuija Takala and Matti Ha¨yry, ‘Genetic Ignorance,
Moral Obligations and Social Duties’, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25 (2000),
pp. 107–113.
The mezzanine rules of ethical genetic databanking 19
Security
Genetic databanks need systems and procedures to secure the privacy
and confidentiality of the people whose samples and records they collect,
store and disseminate; and to ensure the ethical use of the information
with which they are trusted. Security issues can be approached from at
least two angles, which may be complementary.
The promotion of objective security is a matter of safety mechanisms,
data protection, scientific risk assessment and good professional practice
in handling sensitive information. It can be argued that as long as experts
in this field are satisfied with the security of the system, this is, in and by
itself, sufficient.
Another aspect of the matter is, however, the sense of security felt subjectively by individuals, intersubjectively by groups and communities, or
politically by nations and international alliances. Several methods can be
employed to create and enhance this feeling of trust, which may or may
not be a function of the objective measures taken.
In liberal democracies, it is usually held that trust can be rightfully
achieved by the openness and transparency of the system, and by the
honesty and clear accountability of the individuals working within it.9
In
social democracies, it can also be maintained that the political system,
and other systems authorized by it, should be regarded as trustworthy,
unless a significant portion of the citizenship questions this through
democratic processes.
In political environments which do not emphasize democracy, the best
way to lull people into a false sense of security is to inform them only
selectively – perhaps even by concealing facts which could alarm the
public. Since the study of non-democratic responses to genetic databanks
falls outside the scope of the ELSAGEN project, and of this chapter, we
shall not explore it any further. It is worth mentioning, however, that the
widely acclaimed practice of ‘promoting public awareness’ can assume
radically different forms in different political systems. In liberal democracies, the public can be thought to have a duty to know about the facts and
conjectures behind political decisions. In social democracies, the right to
know can be stressed. And in non-democratic societies, people presumably have an obligation to comply with the inevitable. The ‘awareness’ to be
promoted will not be the same in all these cases.
9 On the significance of these, see, e.g., Onora O’Neill, ‘Informed Consent and Genetic
Information’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences
32 (2001), pp. 689–704.
20 Matti Ha¨yry and Tuija Takala