Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

THE CONSTITUTION OF LAW Part 8 pptx
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
172 taking the administrative state seriously
to the impact of public power on human rights before a decision is taken
to exert or delegate authority.
There is also the Select Committee on the Constitution, established
by the House of Lords in 2001, and whose mandate is to examine the
constitutional implications of ‘all public Bills coming before the House;
and to keep under review the operation of the constitution’. While Robert
Hazell has noted that this committee has not yet ‘earned a place as a pillar
of the constitution’, he still emphasizes that it does offer the ‘potential to
do so’.139
As Feldman said in his reflection on his work at the Joint Committee:
‘If human rights are to be properly taken into account at all stages of
the legislative process, Parliament and the executive must work together
and respect each other’s responsibilities and functions. Each must act as
guarantor of the other’s commitment to fundamental values.’140 He went
on to say that ‘friction’ between the different institutions is not only to be
expected but to be welcomed, since institutions which ‘tolerate, and even
celebrate, that friction demonstrate a commitment to human rights . . .
[H]uman rights offer not harmony, but a practical framework in which a
society, if it is sufficiently durable and flexible, can maintain an equilibrium between conflicting interests’.141
In establishing this practical framework, it is, I believe, impossible
to draw any advance distinction between small ‘p’ politics or large ‘P’
politics which could demarcate the area of prerogative or the exceptional
situation where the controls of the rule of law are inappropriate. Indeed,
here I agree with Carl Schmitt though I want to reject the implication
he wished to draw that law cannot control an exceptional situation. This
implication would follow only if it were also impossible to have political
accountability to the rule of law in some situations; for example, if it were
impossible to conceive of an institution such as SIAC. It might take, that is,
institutional imagination, a readiness on the part of legislature, executive
and judiciary to experiment unbound by a rigid doctrine of the separation
of powers, to give full expression to the rule of law. But whether or not one
should do this is not determined by the brute nature of the political, by
the alleged fact that in some category of highly intense political decisions
the rule of law has no grip. Rather, the situation involves a political choice.
Moreover, as I will now suggest, while this choice in a democracy is one
139 Ibid., 499. He also draws attention to the Delegated Powers and Regulatory Reform
Committee, established in 1992; 495–7. 140 Feldman, ‘The Impact of Human Rights on the UK Legislative Process’ 115. 141 Ibid.
in the black hole 173
for the people through their representative body to make, it is not a choice
open to judges, at least it is not open to judges who understand their duty
to uphold the rule of law. Such judges will understand that their duty is to
uphold the values of the rule of law, the constitution of law itself. So I will
now return to the more abstract themes canvassed in the first chapter in
order to answer the questions and challenges posed there, thus bringing
the themes of the whole into one coherent picture of the rule of law.