Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

THE CONSTITUTION OF LAW Part 5 docx
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
anxiety about judicial review of legislation 91
judges, said Willis, invoke their preferred maxims of statutory interpretation ‘not as a means of discovering an unexpressed intent but as a means
of controlling an expressed intent of which they happen to disapprove’.54
I do not wish to deny that these dangers lurk in any aspirational account
of the rule of law, especially one which asserts that there are unwritten
constitutional values which the legislature must respect. However, there
are dangers which lurk in the judicial stance which I have called constitutional positivism, as well as in the position taken by Willis and those
who follow him in the family of positions that make up the positivist tradition, one which we have seen is deeply sceptical of judicial review, and
which has powerful torch bearers today in all three of the Commonwealth
jurisdictions on which I am focusing.
The dangers should be obvious. Whether such judges operate within a
common law or division of powers constitutional order, they cannot qua
judge distinguish between a statute that permits arbitrary detention and a
statute that regulates the most banal activity one can imagine. They might
bleat about how they love rights as much as the next man, but when push
comes to shove it is the rights of the detainee that are shoved.
But there is worse to come. It is one thing for judges to shy away from
invalidating a statute when they have no explicit textual authority to do
so. But it is quite another for them to refuse to interpret a statute in the
light of unwritten constitutional values because, as Willis suggested, such
interpretation is a means of controlling rather than determining intent.
But this is precisely where constitutional positivism leads, something well
illustrated by the recent decision of the Australian High Court in Al-Kateb
v. Godwin,55 a decision which though not about emergency legislation or
national security is clearly one of a number of decisions by judges in the
Commonwealth which are profoundly shaped by judicial sensitivity to
the world after 9/11.
The appellant, Ahmed Al-Kateb, was a stateless person. Section 189 of
the Migration Act 1958 requires the compulsory administrative detention
of unlawful non-citizens; s. 198 provides that an officer must remove an
unlawful non-citizen ‘as soon as reasonably practicable’; s. 196 stipulates
that an unlawful non-citizen detained under s. 189 must be detained
until removed, deported or granted a visa. Section 196(3) prevents the
release even by a court of an unlawfully detained non-citizen except for
removal or deportation (unless the person has been granted a visa). AlKateb’s case raises the issue that this scheme presumes the compliance of
54 Ibid., 276. 55 Al-Kateb v. Godwin (2004) 208 ALR 124.
92 constituting the legislature
another state (in most cases, obviously, the person’s home state) willing to
take such a person. Diplomatic channels had failed to find another state
willing to accept Al-Kateb, and the question then became whether the
legislation requires his permanent detention given the absence of hope
that his removal will ever be ‘reasonably practicable’. Al-Kateb had lost in
the courts below.
The majority – McHugh, Hayne, Callinan and Heydon JJ – dismissed
the appeal. Separate dissents were written by Gleeson CJ, Gummow and
Kirby JJ. While the judgments are quite different, the majority and the
dissents, as least those of Gleeson CJ and Kirby J,56 divide roughly along
the following fault line. The dissenters tend to see the question as one
of statutory interpretation, an enterprise arguably engaging interpretative presumptions along the lines of common law rights and compliance
with international law. The majority, for the most part, saw two main
questions: first, the construction of the statute and, second, a constitutional question: did the legislation correctly construed run afoul of
the Constitution’s Chapter III constitutional protection of judicial power
because it conferred a punitive function on the executive? At its most profound, though, the difference between the two sets of judges boils down to
a view of legal authority, constructed around a view of who is the proper
subject of the law’s protection, who is in the legal community and who
is out. For Kirby J and Gleeson CJ, it is sufficient that an individual is
subject to the law for him to get the protection of the rule of law. For the
majority, a non-citizen is an alien who, depending on his status, will get
something less, and in a case like Al-Kateb’s something far less, than the
full protection of the law.
Gleeson CJ read the provisions of the Act as creating a gap since they
made no express provision for indefinite or permanent detention where
the assumption of the reasonable practicability of removal is false. ‘The
possibility that a person, regardless of personal circumstances, regardless
of whether he or she is a danger to the community, and regardless of
whether he or she might abscond, can be subjected to indefinite, and
perhaps permanent, administrative detention is not one to be dealt with by
implication.’57 Thus he reasoned that one had to resort ‘to a fundamental
principle of interpretation’:58
56 The third dissenting judge, Gummow J, sought for the most part to put his dissent on
a purely textual basis, thus evidencing the same urge to take refuge in constitutional
positivism that we saw in the majority judgments in the Communist Party case. 57 Ibid., at 130. 58 Ibid., at 129.