Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

PRIMATES AND PHILOSOPHERS Part 9 ppsx
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
part of the same community. My disapproval reflects concern about what would happen if everyone started acting
like A: my long-term interest are not served by rampant stealing. This rather abstract yet still egocentric concern about the
quality of life in a community is what underpins the “impartial” and “disinterested” perspective stressed by Philip Kitcher
and Peter Singer, which is at the root of our distinction between right and wrong.
Chimpanzees do distinguish between acceptable and unacceptable behavior, but always closely tied to immediate
consequences, especially for themselves. Thus, apes and
other highly social animals seem capable of developing prescriptive social rules (de Waal 1996; Flack et al. 2004), of
which I will offer just one example:
One balmy evening at the Arnhem Zoo, when the keeper
called the chimps inside, two adolescent females refused to
enter the building. The weather was superb. They had the
whole island to themselves and they loved it. The rule at the
zoo was that none of the apes would get fed until all of them
had moved inside. The obstinate teenagers caused a grumpy
mood among the rest. When they finally did come in, several
hours late, they were assigned a separate bedroom by the
keeper so as to prevent reprisals. This protected them only
temporarily, though. The next morning, out on the island,
the entire colony vented its frustration about the delayed
meal by a mass pursuit ending in a physical beating of the
culprits. That evening, they were the first to come in.
(adapted from de Waal 1996: 89)
However impressive such rule enforcement, our species
goes considerably further in this than any other. From very
young onwards we are subjected to judgments of right and
172 FRANS DE WAAL
wrong, which become so much part of how we see the world
that all behavior shown and all behavior experienced passes
through this filter. We put social thumbscrews on everyone,
making sure that their behavior fits expectations.3 We thus
build reputations in the eyes of others, who may reward
us through so-called “indirect reciprocity” (Trivers 1971;
Alexander 1987).
Moral systems thus impose myriad constraints. Behavior
that promotes a mutually satisfactory group life is generally
considered “right” and behavior that undermines it “wrong.”
Consistent with the biological imperatives of survival and
reproduction, morality strengthens a cooperative society
from which everyone benefits and to which most are prepared to contribute. In this sense Rawls (1972) is on target;
morality functions as a social contract.
Level 3: Judgment and Reasoning
The third level of morality goes even further, and at this
point comparisons with other animals become scarce inRESPONSE 173
3 Our experiments on inequity inversion concerned expectations about reward
division (Brosnan and de Waal 2003; Brosnan et al. 2005). In response to Philip
Kitcher, it should be noted that it is unclear that inequity aversion has much to do
with altruism. Another pillar of human morality, equally important as empathy and
altruism, is reciprocity and resource distribution. The reactions of primates faced
with unequal rewards falls under this domain, showing that they watch what they
gain relative to others. Cooperation is not sustainable without a reasonably equal reward distribution (Fehr and Schmidt 1999). Monkeys and apes react negatively to receiving less than someone else, which is indeed different from reacting negatively to
receiving more, but the two reactions may be related if the second reflects anticipation
of the first (i.e., if individuals avoid taking more so as to forestall negative reactions in
others to such behavior). For a discussion of how these two forms of inequity aversion may relate to the human sense of fairness, see de Waal (2005: 209–11).