Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

PRIMATES AND PHILOSOPHERS Part 8 docx
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
asked what you should do in these circumstances, most people say that you should not push the stranger off the bridge.
Greene and his colleagues see these situations as differing
in the extent to which they involve an “impersonal” situation
such as throwing a switch, or a “personal” violation such as
pushing a stranger off a bridge. They found that when subjects were deciding about the “personal” cases, the parts of
the brain associated with emotional activity were more active than they were when the subjects were asked to make
judgments in “impersonal” cases. More significantly, the minority of subjects who came to the conclusion that it would
be right to act in ways that involve a personal violation, but
minimize harm overall—for example, those who say that it
would be right to push the stranger off the footbridge—
show more activity in parts of the brain associated with cognitive activity, and take longer to reach their decision, than
those who say “no” to such actions.7 In other words, when
confronted with the need to physically assault another person, our emotions are powerfully aroused, and for some, the
fact that this is the only way to save several lives is insufficient to overcome those emotions. But those who are prepared to save as many lives as possible, even if this involves
physically pushing another person to his death, appear to be
using their reason to override their emotional resistance to
the personal violation that pushing another person involves.
Does this lend support for the idea of “human morality as
evolutionarily anchored in mammalian sociality”? Yes, to a
148 P ETER SINGER
7 Joshua Greene and Jonathan Haidt, “How (and Where) Does Moral Judgment
Work,?” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6 (2002): 517–523, and personal communications. To be more specific, those who accept the personal violation show more anterior dorsolateral prefrontal activity, while those who reject it have more activity in
the precuneus area.
point. The emotional responses that lead most people to say
it would be wrong to push a stranger off a footbridge can be
explained in just the kind of evolutionary terms that de Waal
develops in his lectures, and supports with evidence drawn
from his observations of primate behavior. Similarly, it is
easy to see why we would not have developed similar responses to something like throwing a switch, which may also
cause death or injury, but does so at a distance. For all of our
evolutionary history, we have been able to harm people by
pushing them violently, but it is only for a few centuries—
far too brief a time to make a difference to our evolved
nature—that we have been able to harm people by actions
like throwing switches.
Before we take this as confirming de Waal’s point, however, we need to think again about the subjects of Greene’s
research who, after some reflection, come to the conclusion
that just as it is right to throw a switch to divert a train,
killing one person but saving five, so too it is right to push
one person off a footbridge, killing one but saving five. This
is a judgment that other social mammals seem incapable of
making. Yet it too is a moral judgment. It appears to come,
not from the common evolutionary heritage we share with
other social mammals, but from our capacity to reason. Like
the other social mammals, we have automatic, emotional responses to certain kinds of behavior, and these responses
constitute a large part of our morality. Unlike the other social mammals, we can reflect on our emotional responses,
and choose to reject them. Recall Humphrey Bogart’s line in
the closing moments of Casablanca, when, as Rick Blaine, he
tells the woman he loves (Ilsa Lund, played by Ingrid
Bergman) to get on the plane and join her husband: “I’m no
good at being noble, but it doesn’t take much to see that the
COMMENT 149