Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

Moral Status Phần 5 ppt
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
kindly or benevolent feelings, but rather that such emotions must
not be what directs the will towards the performance of duty. To act
from a good will is to act from morally sound principles, and to do
this because it is what reason requires.
But how are we to know which principles of action are morally
sound? Kant proposes a single universal principle, from which all
other moral principles may be derived. This principle, he says, ‘is of
such widespread significance as to hold, not merely for men, but for
all rational beings as such—not merely subject to contingent conditions and expectations, but with absolute necessity’.17 He calls this
principle the Categorical Imperative, by contrast with those imperatives that are hypothetical, i.e. that hold only when the agent has certain goals.
Kant offers several formulations of the Categorical Imperative,
which he regards as logically equivalent. One of the most important
of these is the Formula of Universal Law, which requires that we act
only upon principles that it is rational to want everyone to act upon
at all times. In Kant’s words, ‘I ought never to act except in such a
way that I can also will that my maxim should become a universal
law.’18 The ‘maxim’ is the principle upon which one acts, whether or
not one has ever consciously formulated that principle. The
Categorical Imperative requires us to act only upon maxims which
any rational being could, without contradiction, agree to act upon
all of the time.
One example which Kant uses to illustrate the universalizability
requirement is of a person who obtains money by making a false
promise of repayment. The maxim of such an action, Kant says,
contradicts itself when proposed as a universal moral law, because if
everyone made false promises for personal gain, the very institution
of promising would be destroyed.19 Since it is irrational to will the
universalization of a self-contradictory maxim, we must conclude
that it is always morally wrong to make a false promise.
This formulation of the Categorical Imperative has faced serious
objections. Perhaps the most damaging is that Kant provides no
principled way of determining which elements of the situation may
legitimately be included within our formulation of the maxim of an
action. Thus, it is nearly always possible to formulate a maxim under
Personhood and Moral Rights 97
17 Ibid. 67. 18 Ibid. 19 Ibid. 85.
chap. 4 4/30/97 3:09 PM Page 97
which an action falls, which a rational being could without self-contradiction will to become universal law. For instance, if you wish to
make a false promise in order to obtain money, you may formulate
the maxim that it is permissible to make a false promise when the
circumstances are exactly like the ones in which you find yourself.
This is a maxim that could be universalized without self-contradiction, since there will be very few cases in which a rational being is in
exactly the same situation that you are; hence the institution of
promise making would be in little danger if that maxim were universally followed. But the objections to this formulation of the
Categorical Imperative need not concern us further, since there is
another formulation which is more directly relevant to Kant’s defence of the Personhood Only view.
Persons as Ends in Themselves
A second formulation of the Categorical Imperative is what Kant
calls the Formula of the End in Itself. In his words,
man, and in general every rational being, exists as an end in himself, not
merely as a means for arbitrary use by this or that will: he must in all his
actions, whether they are directed to himself or to other rational beings,
always be viewed at the same time as an end.
20
To treat persons as ends in themselves is to treat them as having
‘dignity’, or ‘intrinsic value’. This is a value ‘which is exalted above
all price, and so admits of no equivalent’.21 Because persons are
ends in themselves, their autonomy must be respected, not just as
one component of utility, but as something that imposes strict constraints upon the ways in which they may be treated. There is nothing wrong with treating persons as means to ends that they have
accepted; we do this in all co-operative human activities. It is, however, wrong to treat persons as if they were mere means, things that
we are entitled to use towards ends that are not their own. Because
we could not rationally agree to being treated as mere means, maxims that allow us to treat other persons as mere means cannot consistently be willed to become universal law; thus, the two
formulations of the Categorical Imperative turn out to be substantially equivalent.
98 An Account of Moral Status
20 The Moral Law, 90. 21 Ibid. 96.
chap. 4 4/30/97 3:09 PM Page 98