Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

Moral Status Phần 4 pdf
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
jects. ‘If it really were possible’, he says, ‘to save many lives by an experiment that would take just one life, and there were no other way
those lives could be saved, it might be right to do the experiment.’57
3.4. Objections to the Sentience Only View
The conclusions that Singer draws from the principle of equal consideration entail that many of us should change our daily behaviour,
especially our diets. Yet these conclusions are more consistent with
practical necessity than are some of the implications of the Life
Only view. While no one can exist without causing the deaths of
many living things, most people could lead satisfactory lives without
consuming animal products that are produced in inhumane ways.58
Some people gain important medical benefits from the continued
use of animals in biomedical research; but equivalent expenditures
on education, housing, and other social needs might produce as
great an overall improvement in human welfare, with less nonhuman suffering.
Unfortunately, the Sentience Only view has implications which
are more troubling than the ones that Singer emphasizes. There are
four potentially fatal objections to the principle of equal consideration. Three of these—the environmentalist, Humean/feminist, and
human rights objections—spotlight problematic consequences of
the view that sentience is the only valid criterion of moral status.
The fourth objection involves some implications of the principle of
equal consideration which I argue are impossible to reconcile with
the demands of practical necessity.
The Environmentalist Objection
Many environmental ethicists reject the Sentience Only view because
it denies moral status to plants, species, and other non-sentient elements of the biosphere.59 On the Sentience Only view, we may have
Sentience and the Utilitarian Calculus 71
57 Ibid. 78. 58 There are, however, questions about the nutritional adequacy of a vegan diet
for pregnant and nursing women, and young children. See Kathryn Paxton George,
‘Should Feminists be Vegetarians?’, Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society,
19, No. 2 (Winter 1994), 405–34. 59 For instance, Rolston, Environmental Ethics (Philadelphia, Pa.: Temple
chap. 3 4/30/97 3:03 PM Page 71
morally sound reasons to protect these things, but these reasons can
only be based upon the interests of sentient beings, since non-sentient entities have no interests that can enter directly into our moral
calculations. Species, Singer says, ‘are not conscious entities and so
do not have interests above and beyond the interests of the individual animals that are members of the species’.60 We have, therefore,
no moral obligations to species as such.
In contrast, deep ecologists argue that natural plant and animal
species, populations, and habitats can all have moral status. Aldo
Leopold, the intellectual founder of the contemporary environmentalist movement, called for an ethic in which human beings are seen
as members of the biological community, having moral obligations
to the community’s other members.61 Within such an ethic, an organism’s moral status is based upon its ecosystemic relationships to
the rest of the biosphere. Leopold would probably have agreed, for
instance, that it is more important to protect the remaining stands
of bishop pines on the California coast than the wild radishes that
grow by the roadsides there. For the pines are an important and vulnerable part of the indigenous plant community; while the radishes
are hardy European imports which are in no danger of disappearing.62
On the Sentience Only view, such considerations are irrelevant to
moral status. Trees—however vital to the ecosystem—have no more
moral status than wild radishes. To many environmentalists, a theory which allows us to have moral obligations regarding the non-sentient elements of the natural world but never to them, seems just as
inadequate as the Kantian theory, which allows us to have duties regarding animals, but never to them. John Rodman recounts that he
first perceived a particular piece of California coastal chaparral ‘in
terms of sagebrush, scrub oak, and cactus’, and only later learned
that it was also home to dusky-footed woodrats. ‘On reflection,’ he
72 An Account of Moral Status
University Press, 1988), 94, 146; and J. Baird Callicott, ‘On the Intrinsic Value of
Nonhuman Species’, in Bryan G. Norton (ed.), The Preservation of Species
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1988), 280–4.
60 Peter Singer, ‘Not for Humans Only: The Place of Nonhumans in
Environmental Ethics’, in K. E. Goodpaster and K. M. Sayre (eds.), Ethics and the
Problems of the 21st Century (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press,
1979), 203. 61 Aldo Leopold, A Sand County Almanac (New York: Ballantine Books, 1970). 62 The pine is Pinus muricata, the radish, Raphanus sativus.
chap. 3 4/30/97 3:03 PM Page 72