Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

Imperialism, Sovereignty and the Making of International Law Part 8 docx
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
252 imperialism, sovereignty and international law
precisely because French traders, for example, were denied access to
British colonies.
The ‘right to trade’ and the assessment of non-European government
in terms of its recognition of the right to trade has been a continuous theme of the discipline. When companies such as the British East
India Company, exercising sovereign rights, administered the territories
of non-European peoples, they established systems of law and governance that were directed at furthering the commercial relations that
were the very sine qua non of their existence. Commerce and governance
were not merely complementary but identical: a corporation exercised
the power of government. The governance of non-European territories
was assessed principally on the basis of whether it enabled Europeans to
live and trade as they wished. Thus, according to Westlake, non-European
states were uncivilized unless they could provide a system of government
‘under the protection of which . . . the former [Europeans] may carry on
the complex life to which they have been accustomed in their homes’.22 If
such government was lacking, Westlake argued, ‘government should be
furnished’.23 Capitulation systems, protectorate arrangements and outright conquest could remedy the situation.
The explicit association between governance and commerce was gradually elaborated over time to establish a more morally nuanced justification for commerce and colonialism, after the decline of trading
companies and the direct engagement of European governments in the
imperial enterprise. Thus, during the Berlin Conference -- which was preoccupied precisely with the orderly exploitation of Africa by the great
European powers -- commerce was characterized by Bismarck as a crucial means of spreading civilization itself. The link between commerce
and civilization was further elaborated, of course, through the concept
of the dual mandate, as developed by Chamberlain and Lugard: ‘We
develop new territory as Trustees of Civilisation for the Commerce of
the World.’24 In these ways, the expansion of European commerce was
not understood as a mechanism for the economic exploitation and subordination of non-European peoples, but rather, a means of effecting the
entry of the backward peoples into the world of civilization. Humanitarian goals were furthered precisely through the expansion of commerce,
22 John Westlake, Chapters on the Principles of International Law (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1894), p. 141. 23 Ibid., p. 142. 24 Lord Lugard, The Dual Mandate in British Tropical Africa (Hamden, CT: Archon Books
1965), epigraph.
g ov e r n a nc e a n d g l o b a l i z a t i o n 253
and appropriate systems of government had to be formulated for this
purpose. Even while driven by commerce, the humanitarian aspect of
the rhetoric of governance developed an extraordinarily complex and
resilient character such that, in the new framework of the dual mandate, all manner of economic policies, could now be justified and refined
as advancing humanitarian causes.
My overall argument, then, is that the non-European world is different, that the governance of these societies has been intimately shaped,
since the very beginnings of the colonial encounter, by international
actors, imperial European states, whose actions have been sanctioned
and enabled by international law. It is hardly surprising, then, that
the governance of non-European societies was a subject of considerable
scholarship, and that authors such as M. F. Lindley compiled, described
and analysed these techniques of governance in 1926, in a book revealingly titled, for example, The Acquisition and Government of Backward Territory in International Law.
25 At a time when government within European
states was entirely immune to regulation by international law, government in non-European states was a matter which international law could
dictate. It must be noted that the purpose of this exercise was often to
grant the indigenous peoples some measure of protection. But the fundamental purposes animating governance, of furthering civilization and
commerce, remained the same.
Contemporary debates on governance focus largely on the relations
between the governors and the governed, the relations between the
state and its citizens, the individuals whose democratic rights must
be protected, or whose standards of living must be elevated. My argument, however, is that, historically, the international legal discourse
on government has been shaped not so much by a concern for the
governed -- although invariably some reference is made to them -- but
by a concern to impose ‘universal standards’ that essentially furthered
European/ Western interests. This history of governance exerts an enduring and powerful pressure on the present. The relationship between
globalization and governance can be seen, I suggest, in the same way:
governance is now designed to provide the political institutions that
will enable the furtherance of globalization. Specifically, this is to be
achieved through the international human rights norms that are seen
25 For other examples of this genre, see Charles G. Fenwick, Wardship in International Law
(Washington, DC: Government Printing Office, 1919); Alpheus H. Snow, The Question of
Aborigines in the Law and Practice of Nations (New York: Putnam, 1921).
254 imperialism, sovereignty and international law
as prescribing universally accepted international standards and which
are used as a basis to further governance.
Governance, human rights and the universal
The emergence of international human rights law is among the most
significant developments to have occurred in the field of international
law and relations during the UN period which has been termed, ‘The
Age of Rights’ by Louis Henkin. Human rights law is revolutionary
because it purports to regulate the behaviour of a sovereign within its
own territory. The emergence of Third World societies, as independent
sovereign states, was simultaneous with the creation of international
human rights law, which significantly conditioned the character of that
sovereignty. The sovereign non-European state, then, never possessed the
absolute power over its own territory and people that was exercised by
the nineteenth-century European state. Further, to the extent that international human rights law and nationalism represent Western ideas
of the individual, state and society they both create the paradox that
Third World sovereignty was exercised through, and shaped by, Western
structures.
Given the universality of human rights and its aspiration to regulate state action with respect to the individual, it is unsurprising that
‘good governance’ should be conceptually and operationally linked with
international human rights law and that it enjoys a certain legitimacy
and coherence as a result. While the question of the universality of
international human rights law has always been debated, developments
following the end of the Cold War raised this issue in a particularly
contentious way. This occurred in part because Western governments
and other entities sought to universalise the political institutions of
the liberal democratic state by elaborating models of ‘democratic governance’ and ‘legitimate governance’ through international human rights
law. In his scrupulous examination of Article 25, the Right to Political Participation enunciated in the International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights (ICCPR), Henry Steiner concluded in 1988 that Article 25
was an open and programmatic right that could be tailored in various
ways to the particular social and cultural conditions and traditions of
a society.26 By contrast, in his 1992 article on the same matter, Gregory
26 Steiner, ‘Political Participation’.