Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

Tài liệu Regulatory Rights Supreme Court Activism, the Public Interest, and the Making of
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
Regulatory Rights
Regulatory Rights
Supreme Court Activism, the
Public Interest, and the Making of
Constitutional Law
larry yackle
the university of chicago press chicago and london
larry yackle is professor of law and the Basil Yanakakis Research Scholar at Boston
University School of Law. He has taught and written about constitutional law throughout
his academic career, and he is the author of fi ve other books, including Reform and Regret
and Reclaiming the Federal Courts.
The University of Chicago Press, Chicago 60637
The University of Chicago Press, Ltd., London
© 2007 by The University of Chicago
All rights reserved. Published 2007
Printed in the United States of America
16 15 14 13 12 11 10 09 08 07 1 2 3 4 5
isbn-13: 978-0-226-94471-5 (cloth)
isbn-10: 0-226-94471-9 (cloth)
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Yackle, Larry W.
Regulatory rights : Supreme Court activism, the public interest, and the making of
constitutional law / Larry Yackle.
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN-13: 978-0-226-94471-5 (cloth : alk. paper)
ISBN-10: 0-226-94471-9 (cloth : alk. paper)
1. Constitutional law—United States—Interpretation and construction. 2. Police
power—United States. 3. United States. Supreme Court. 4. Civil rights—United
States. I. Title.
KF4552 .Y33 2007
342.73—dc22
2007005605
The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of the Ameri can
National Standard for Information Sciences—Permanence of Paper for Printed Library
Materials, ansi z39.48-1992.
for jeanette
Contents
Acknowledgments xi
Introduction 1
1. The Documentary Constitution 11
Constitutional Law 13
Explanations 15
The Constancy of a Writing 15
The Legitimacy of a Compact 19
A Constitution Made by Judges 23
Textualism 25
Yawning Gaps 27
Vague and Ambiguous Terms 29
The Analogy to Statutes 30
The Text Writ Large 31
The Text in Context 32
Negative Examples 35
Originalism 40
The Framers 41
The Founding Generation 47
More Negative Examples 48
2. Constitutional Common Law 52
Rights 57
Natural Rights 58
Rights and Formalism 61
The Positive Present 62
Markets 64
The Unregulated Baseline 64
The Regulatory Present 66
The Public Interest 68
Natural Rights (Again) 68
The Police Power 70
Formalism (Again) 72
Laissez-Faire 74
Class Legislation 76
Effi ciency and Elections 79
3. Regulatory Rights 83
Preliminaries 84
Restraints Neither Internal nor External 84
Regulatory Rights in the Literature 87
Due Process 94
The Substance of Process 95
Market Freedom 97
Fundamental Interests 99
Procedural Rights 101
Substantive Rights 101
Beyond the Bill of Rights 102
Abusive Behavior 104
Equal Protection 106
Equality and Purpose 107
The Overlap with Due Process 108
Classifi cations 113
Ordinary Classifi cations 113
Fundamental Interests (Again) 114
Suspicious Classifi cations 114
Freedom of Expression 115
Free Speech 116
Freedom of Religion 119
Cruel and Unusual Punishments 120
4. Rational Instrumentalism 125
Standards of Review 126
The Rational-Basis Test 128
Close Scrutiny 129
Means 135
The Level-of-Generality Question 135
Disproportionate Impact 139
VIII CONTENTS
Knowing a Means by Its Purpose 144
Individual Interests 144
Rights (Again) 145
The Level-of-Generality Question (Again) 148
Ends 152
The Search for Purpose 153
Techniques 157
Illustrations 158
A Purpose to Work With 159
Compelling Objectives 163
Impermissible Explanations 167
Tautological Ends 168
Of Conduct and Status 169
Conclusion 172
Notes 175
Index 253
CONTENTS IX
Acknowledgments
Numerous friends and colleagues helped me with this project, among
them Winston Bowman, Robert Brickman, Krikor Dekermenjian, Morton J. Horwitz, William Kaleva, Pnina Lahav, Gary Lawson, David
Lyons, Tracey Maclin, Michael Meurer, Ryann M. Muir, Teresa Gallego
O’Rourke, Mark Pettit, H. Jefferson Powell, David Seipp, Aviam Soifer,
and Jeanette Yackle.
Introduction
Supreme Court justices are an aging tribe. Their longevity is a product
of the legal safeguards established to ensure their independence.
They are entitled to serve (and keep on serving) during “good behavior,” which means (in practical effect) as long as they want to. And they
invariably want to for a very long time. The justices now in place are an
especially elderly lot. Then again, they, too, are mortal. Vacancies occasionally appear to be fi lled by comparatively youthful men and women
whose nominations evoke heated debate. Most arguments regarding individual candidates are packaged as claims about Supreme Court justices’ proper function once they are on the bench. We are told, in particular, that justices should not create constitutional rights; rather, they
should enforce the rights the Constitution enshrines. In this book, I hope
to convince you that arguments of that kind fundamentally misconceive
the work justices do and, beyond that, the character of the American
Constitution in whose name they do it. If we can once get the job description right, we will understand why battles over nominees are hardfought and worth fi ghting. It matters who sits on the Supreme Court; it
matters a great deal. It matters because the justices do create individual
constitutional rights—the only rights we have, the only rights we have
ever had, and the only rights we can hope to have.
I mean to argue that substantive federal constitutional rights draw
their meaning exclusively from the great body of relevant Supreme Court
2 INTRODUCTION
decisions and that the only content those rights enjoy, abstracted from
the Court’s decisions, can be reduced to a single doctrinal idea: Government acts constitutionally if it acts instrumentally, adopting policy as a
sensible means of achieving public ends. This is an unorthodox claim. I
do not propose merely that instrumentalism fi gures in the common understanding of rights associated with the Constitution. No one doubts
that. Scarcely any doctrinal formulation is more commonplace. Rational
instrumentalism is ubiquitous in the Court’s treatment of discrete provisions of the historical document adopted in 1789 (and subsequently
amended twenty-seven ways), in the themes commonly inferred from the
document as a whole, and in the underlying theories the document is
said to embody. My argument runs deeper. With respect to the content
of substantive individual rights, instrumentalism occupies the fi eld entirely. Nothing else matters—not the textual provisions conventionally
thought to establish rights, not the history behind those provisions, not
the philosophical notions with which the Constitution is associated. I
contend that rational instrumentalism is far more than a common element circulating through many bodies of constitutional law regarding
substantive rights. Instrumentalism is the central doctrinal idea around
which all else circulates.
I limit my claim to substantive rights—namely, rights that impede governmental action in the interest of individual freedom. Much the same
argument might be advanced with respect to procedural rights, which
generally govern the administration of substantive policies in particular
instances. There, too, the text of the historical document does precious
little work, rational instrumentalism a great deal more. But I make no
effort to develop that argument. Nor do I contend that the text is irrelevant, and rational instrumentalism pervasive, with respect to constitutional concepts apart from individual rights. Provisions of the written
Constitution do prescribe the basic nature and architecture of American
government—for example, provisions explicitly calling for periodic elections and bicameralism in the legislative branch and implicitly for the
separation of national powers and federalism.1
I do think that when the
Court takes up questions about those arrangements, the text itself offers
little guidance. The answers the justices deliver rest on judgment, which,
in turn, is often informed by means-ends instrumentalism.2
But I do not
press those arguments here.
My claim regarding substantive rights is conceptual in the modest
sense that it locates constitutional signifi cance at some remove from the