Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

Responsible belief: a theory in ethics and epistemology
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
i
RESPONSIBLE BELIEF
ii
1
iii
RESPONSIBLE BELIEF
A Theory in Ethics and Epistemology
Rik Peels
1
iv
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers
the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education
by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University
Press in the UK and certain other countries.
Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press
198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America.
© Oxford University Press 2017
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in
a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the
prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted
by law, by license, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reproduction
rights organization. Inquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the
above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the
address above.
You must not circulate this work in any other form
and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer.
CIP data is on file at the Library of Congress
ISBN 978–0–19–060811–8
1 3 5 7 9 8 6 4 2
Printed by Sheridan Books, Inc., United States of America
v
To Herman Philipse
Ferrum ferro acuitur et homo exacuit
faciem amici sui (Proverbia 27:17)
vi
vii
vii
CONTENTS
Acknowledgments xi
Introduction: Why Responsible Belief Matters 1
I.1 Responsible Belief and Blameworthy Belief 1
I.2 Aim of the Book 3
I.3 Why We Need an Account
of Responsible Belief 6
I.4 A New Approach: Intellectual Obligations
and Doxastic Excuses 8
I.5 Outline 11
1. Doxastic Responsibility: What Is It? 14
1.1 Introduction 14
1.2 Responsibility and Appraisal 15
1.3 Occurrent, Dormant, and Tacit Belief 28
1.4 Responsible Belief Is Blameless Belief 43
1.5 Conclusion 51
C ontents
viii
viii
2. The Problem: Doxastic Control
and Doxastic Obligations 52
2.1 Introduction 52
2.2 The Argument from Doxastic Involuntarism 53
2.3 Obligations and Control 56
2.4 First Response: We Have Direct Intentional
Doxastic Control 61
2.5 Second Response: We Have Indirect
Intentional Doxastic Control 66
2.6 Third Response: We Have Compatibilist
Doxastic Control 72
2.7 Fourth Response: Doxastic Obligations
Without Any Kind of Control 81
2.8 Conclusion 87
3. The Solution: Doxastic Influence
and Intellectual Obligations 89
3.1 Introduction 89
3.2 Belief-influencing Factors 90
3.3 What Are Intellectual Obligations? 96
3.4 What Intellectual Obligations Do We Have? 100
3.5 Six Objections and Replies 108
3.6 Intellectual Obligations and Responsible Belief 117
3.7 Doxastic Excuses: Force, Ignorance, and Luck 124
3.8 Conclusion 130
4. Responsible Belief Entails the Ability
to Believe Otherwise 132
4.1 Introduction 132
4.2 What Is Force? 134
4.3 Force as a Doxastic Excuse 137
4.4 Blameworthy Force 143
C ontents
ix
ix
4.5 Control over or Influence on Properties
of Beliefs 148
4.6 Doxastic Frankfurt-style Scenarios 150
4.7 The Doxastic Asymmetry Objection 157
4.8 Conclusion 162
5. Responsible Belief Is Radically Subjective 164
5.1 Introduction 164
5.2 What Is Ignorance? 165
5.3 Ignorance as a Doxastic Excuse 169
5.4 Ignorance as a Narrow and a Broad
Doxastic Excuse 182
5.5 Blameworthy Belief and the Regress Problem 185
5.6 Conclusion 198
6. Responsible Belief Is Compatible
with Doxastic Luck 199
6.1 Introduction 199
6.2 What Is Luck? 200
6.3 Four Varieties of Doxastic Luck and Luck as
a Doxastic Excuse 207
6.4 Consequential Luck and Accidentality 215
6.5 The Problem of Doxastic Luck 218
6.6 Conclusion 234
Appendix: Responsible Belief and Epistemically Justified Belief 237
Bibliography 251
Index 267
x
xi
xi
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
My first encounter with philosophy took place when it was around five
o’clock in the morning. As a fifteen-year-old, I participated in a twentyfour-hour class marathon to raise money for some charity organization.
Ieke Haarsma, who taught philosophy at my school, asked us whether
plants can sleep. I first considered this a silly question—of course plants
cannot sleep. In fact—just to assure the reader—I still think plants
cannot sleep. Upon further consideration, however, it seemed to me
not as obvious why precisely we should think that plants cannot sleep.
Ever since that little event early in the morning, philosophy has gained
increasing importance in my life. What started as an intellectual game
has become for me a highly influential method for approaching, understanding, and sometimes even changing reality. Indeed, it has become
an inalienable part of my own identity, bringing along both the advantages and disadvantages of a philosophical life. I thank Ieke Haarsma for
introducing me to the wonderful world of philosophy.
I could not have written this book without the help, support, and
critical feedback from my colleagues and students at the Philosophy
Departments of Utrecht University and the Vrije Universiteit
Amsterdam. These departments, as well as the Philosophy Department
of Oxford University during Hilary and Trinity terms 2011, have
A cknowledgments
xii
xii
provided a stimulating research environment in which working on this
project was a true pleasure.
Much of the material of this book was presented in some earlier (and,
I am afraid, often premature) version at several conferences. I thank
the audiences for their searching questions and helpful suggestions at
the conference on Doxastic Agency and Epistemic Responsibility at the
University of Bochum, Germany; the Fifth Annual Dutch OZSW
Conference at the Erasmus University of Rotterdam, the Netherlands;
the Fourth Annual Dutch Conference on Practical Philosophy at the
Technological University Eindhoven, the Netherlands; the Epistemology
Meeting: Doxastic Attitudes at Ghent University, Belgium; the 85th
Joint Session of the Aristotelian Society and the Mind Association at
the University of Sussex, United Kingdom; the Second Annual Dutch
Conference on Practical Philosophy at the University of Groningen, the
Netherlands; the conference on Moral Responsibility: Neuroscience,
Organization, and Engineering at the Technological University of Delft,
the Netherlands; the Meta-ethics and Moral Psychology Study Group at
Utrecht University; the 19th Inter-university Workshop on Philosophy
and Cognitive Science at the University of Zaragoza, Spain; the conference on Recent Trends in Philosophy of Language and General Analytic
Philosophy at Tilburg University, the Netherlands; The Young European
Epistemologists Workshop and the Epistemic Agency Conference at
the University of Geneva; the conference on Responsible Belief in the
Face of Disagreement, the First and Second Workshops in Analytic
Philosophy; and the conference on The Value of Knowledge at the Vrije
Universiteit Amsterdam.
For their careful reading and rigorous comments on the entire
book, I would like to thank Tony Booth, René van Woudenberg, and
Ralph Wedgwood. I am heavily indebted to them. I would also like
to thank Matthias Steup and Nicholas Wolterstorff who reviewed the
manuscript for Oxford University Press and went to great lengths to
provide helpful comments. These have led to the rewriting of many
confused and unclear passages. I would also like to thank Niko
Nottelmann; I have benefited immensely from many enjoyable discussions with him on a large number of the issues dealt with in this
book.
A cknowledgments
xiii
xiii
For their astute comments on one or several parts (of earlier versions
or presentations) of the book, I would like to thank Joel Anderson, Max
Baker-Hytch, Arianna Betti, Martijn Blaauw, Martijn Boot, Gerhard
Bos, Niek Brunsveld, Adam Carter, Bob Coenraats, Lieven Decock,
Boudewijn de Bruin, Leon de Bruin, Henk de Regt, Jeroen de Ridder,
Catarina Dutilh Novaes, Richard Feldman, Mikkel Gerken, Jeffrey
Glick, Alvin Goldman, John Greco, Dirk-Martin Grube, Peter Hacker,
Paul Helm, Peter Kirschenmann, Hilary Kornblith, Andrea Kruse,
Pierre Le Morvan, Joop Leo, Clayton Littlejohn, Sebastian Lutz, Rosja
Mastop, Conor McHugh, Anne Meylan, Jesse Mulder, Fred Muller,
Thomas Müller, Bert Musschenga, Philip Nickel, Dawa Ometto, Marina
Oshana, Alvin Plantinga, Stefan Roski, Emanuel Rutten, Marcel
Sarot, Katrien Schaubroeck, Jeroen Smid, Michael Smith, Nicholas
Southwood, Matthias Steup, Derek Strijbos, Jesper Tijmstra, Dorette
van der Tholen, Janneke van Lith, Gert van den Brink, Jessica van der
Schalk, Vincent van Oostrom, Han van Wietmarschen, Albert Visser,
Jan Vorstenbosch, Heinrich Wansing, Brian Weatherson, Jan Willem
Wieland, Timothy Williamson, and Michael Zimmerman.
I thank the Templeton World Charity Foundation, through whose
support publication of this book was made possible. The opinions
expressed in this publication are mine and do not necessarily reflect the
views of Templeton World Charity Foundation.
A heartfelt thank you to my executive editor, Peter Ohlin, my production editors Emily Sacharin and Radha Subburathnam, and my copy
editor Johanna Baboukis, for their continual encouragement and their
hard work to make the publication of this book possible.
Several of the ideas and arguments in this book are based on work
that I published previously. Much of it has undergone substantial
revision—hopefully for the better—but many of the core ideas survived
and made it into this manuscript. I thank the editors involved for their
kind permission to use this material.
The final section of chapter 1 is based on “Why Responsible Belief
Is Blameless Belief ” (co-authored with Anthony Booth), The Journal
of Philosophy 107.5 (2010), 257–265. The main body of chapter 2
is derived from “Against Doxastic Compatibilism,” Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 89.3 (2014), 679–702. The paragraphs on
A cknowledgments
xiv
xiv
belief-policies in chapter 3 summarize what I argue in “Belief-Policies
Cannot Ground Doxastic Responsibility,” Erkenntnis 78.3 (2013), 561–
569. The main body of chapter 4 draws from material published in “Does
Doxastic Responsibility Entail the Ability to Believe Otherwise?,”
Synthese 190.17 (2013), 3651–3669.
The first section of chapter 5, on the nature of ignorance, makes
use of material from “What Is Ignorance?,” Philosophia 38.1 (2010),
57–67, “Ignorance Is Lack of True Belief: A Rejoinder to Le Morvan,”
Philosophia 39.2 (2011), 345–355, and “The New View on Ignorance
Undefeated,” Philosophia 40.4 (2012), 741–750. The main argument of
the chapter can be found in an earlier version in “What Kind of Ignorance
Excuses? Two Neglected Issues,” Philosophical Quarterly 64.256 (2014),
478–496. The final section draws on material from “Tracing Culpable
Ignorance,” Logos and Episteme 2.4 (2011), 575–582.
The parts of chapter 6 on the nature of luck and the problem of
doxastic luck are based on “A Modal Solution to the Problem of Moral
Luck,” American Philosophical Quarterly 64.256 (2015), 478–496.
The Appendix makes use of material from “Let’s Bite the Bullet on
Deontological Epistemic Justification: A Response to Robert Lockie,”
Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 4.12 (2015), 42–49, and
can be found in a more elaborate form in “Epistemic Justification and
Responsible Belief,” Synthese (2016), forthcoming.
Finally, I would like to thank Herman Philipse, who was also my
PhD supervisor, for his many invaluable, constructive comments.
I especially want to thank him for his hospitality and the fun we had during our memorable fortnightly paper discussion sessions at his home.
Even, or maybe especially, where our views do not seem to converge,
such as our opinions in the philosophy of religion, his ideas and criticisms have been greatly inspiring for me. It is to him that I dedicate this
book, with gratitude.