Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

In Defense of Animals Part 3 ppt
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
On the Question of Personhood beyond Homo sapiens
43
something, permitting us to identify paradigm persons and, beyond these
easy cases, other individuals who are sufficiently similar to warrant inclusion
under the concept.
Do we know of any persons, extinct or currently living, beyond Homo
sapiens?
Other Hominid Persons
Normal children of our species, Homo sapiens, are among the paradigm
persons. Surely, then, at least some members of other hominid species were
also persons, for there is no reason to think they were all vastly less
endowed with personhood-relevant properties than human children are. Let
me explain.
Although ours is the only surviving hominid species, hominid evolution
featured various others, including Homo erectus, Homo habilis, Homo rudolfensis,
Australopithecus africanus, Australopithecus robustus, and others. Interestingly,
two of the great ape species, chimpanzees and bonobos, and the various
hominid species, including ours, had a common ancestor who lived only 5
to 7 million years ago (Dawkins 1993: 82; see also Hecht 2003).
Now consider whichever hominid species we evolved from. Typical members of that species were genetically a bit different from us. Yet it is hardly
plausible that no members of that species were sufficiently like our (normal)
human children – who are clearly persons – to qualify as persons. Indeed,
there is no natural marker that could separate the two species in the course
of evolution; it is not as if some decisive mutation created a massive gulf
dividing us from our immediate predecessors. Any dividing line in hominid
evolution would be something to draw in an arbitrarily chosen place at least
as much as a biological reality to find. So, because normal human children
are clearly persons, at least some hominids who were not Homo sapiens were
persons as well. Therefore, in actual fact and not just science fiction and
speculative religion, there have been persons beyond Homo sapiens.
One might object that, since our concept of personhood is relatively
modern, it makes no sense to attribute it to prehistoric hominids. But the
objection is confused. While our concept of personhood is modern, the concept designates a kind of being with certain complex forms of consciousness.
Such beings existed long before any arrived at the modern concept, just as
plutonium and dinosaurs existed long before anyone employed the concepts
of plutonium and dinosaurs.
IDOC03 43 11/5/05, 8:59 AM
David DeGrazia
44
Ordinary Great Apes and Dolphins as
Borderline Persons
Even if hominid evolution featured some persons beyond our species, one
might argue, there are no known cases of living nonhuman persons. But
as the only candidates we know are terrestrial beings, this contention begs
the question of whether any nonhuman animals are persons. I will argue
that normal representatives of the great ape and certain cetacean species
are borderline persons, lying in an ambiguous gray area between paradigm
persons and those who are clearly not persons.
To which animals are we referring? The great apes include (“common”)
chimpanzees, bonobos (sometimes called “pygmy chimpanzees”), gorillas,
and orangutans. Sometimes for convenience I will refer to great apes simply
as “apes” – although there are also “lesser apes,” gibbons and siamangs, to
whom I will not be referring. Cetaceans include all whales, including the
smaller whales known as dolphins (of the family Delphinidae) and porpoises
(of the family Phocoenidae). Sometimes the term “dolphin” is used broadly
to include both of these families of smaller whales, and for convenience
I will adopt this broader usage. Available evidence suggests that apes and
dolphins are the most cognitively, emotionally, and socially advanced
nonhuman animals, making them the best known candidates for presently
living nonhuman persons.
Let’s briefly review some of this evidence, beginning with the great apes.
Although their capacity for intentional action is evident in virtually everything they do, it is especially apparent in certain activities that express unusual deliberateness, reasoning, or planning. For example, chimpanzees
regularly use tools such as moss for a sponge, stems as probes for insects,
and rocks as nut-crackers (see, e.g., McGrew 1992: 44–6). Meanwhile, all
of the apes engage in social manipulation, including deception, of their
fellows (see, e.g., Byrne 1996; de Waal 1997: 39–40; Tomasello and Call
1997: 235–59). Further, apes are self-aware in more than one way. Bodily
self-awareness, which is manifested in all intentional action, is more impressively revealed in apes’ imitation of bodily gestures,3
use of mirrors to
investigate otherwise inaccessible markings on their own bodies,4
and use
of televised images of their out-of-view arms to reach hidden objects (see
Tomasello and Call 1997: 52). Social self-awareness, meanwhile, is evident
in apes’ natural social structures, which feature dominance hierarchies,
long-term relationships, and shifting allegiances; individuals need to know
IDOC03 44 11/5/05, 8:59 AM