Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

Forensic evidence
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
Terrence F. Kiely
FORENSIC
EVIDENCE:
SCIENCE AND THE
CRIMINAL LAW
Boca Raton London New York Washington, D.C.
CRC Press
©2001 CRC Press LLC
This book contains information obtained from authentic and highly regarded sources. Reprinted material
is quoted with permission, and sources are indicated. A wide variety of references are listed. Reasonable
efforts have been made to publish reliable data and information, but the author and the publisher cannot
assume responsibility for the validity of all materials or for the consequences of their use.
Neither this book nor any part may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic
or mechanical, including photocopying, microfilming, and recording, or by any information storage or
retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publisher.
The consent of CRC Press LLC does not extend to copying for general distribution, for promotion, for
creating new works, or for resale. Specific permission must be obtained in writing from CRC Press LLC
for such copying.
Direct all inquiries to CRC Press LLC, 2000 N.W. Corporate Blvd., Boca Raton, Florida 33431.
Trademark Notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are
used only for identification and explanation, without intent to infringe.
© 2001 by CRC Press LLC
No claim to original U.S. Government works
International Standard Book Number 0-8493-1896-3
Library of Congress Card Number 00-037856
Printed in the United States of America 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0
Printed on acid-free paper
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Kiely, Terrence F.
Forensic evidence : science and the criminal law / Terrence F. Kiely
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-8493-1896-3 (alk. paper)
1. Evidence, Expert--United States. 2. Forensic sciences--United States. I. Title.
KF8961 .K54 2000
345.73′067−−dc21 00-037856
©2001 CRC Press LLC
If any Man be delighted in History, let him read the Books of Law, which are nothing
else but Annals and Chronicles of Things done and acted upon from year to year, in
which each Case presents you with a petit history; and if Variety of Matter doth most
delight the reader, doubtless, the reading of those Cases, (which differ like Men’s
Faces), tho like the Stars in Number, is the most pleasant reading in the World.
—Giles Duncombe
Trials per Pais, or the Law of England Concerning Juries by Nisi Prius (1725)
. . .
For without Victory at the Trial, to what Purpose is the Science of the Law? The
Judge can give no Sentence, no decision without it, and must give Judgement for
that Side the Trial goes; therefore I may well say, tis the chief Part of the Practice
of the Law. And if so, to whom shall I offer this Treatise, but to you the Practisers?
—Giles Duncombe
Trials per Pais, or the Law of England Concerning Juries by Nisi Prius (1725)
©2001 CRC Press LLC
Preface
Forensic Evidence: Science and the Criminal Law is intended to serve as an introduction and guide to the appreciation and understanding of the significant historical,
contemporary, and future relationship between the world of the forensic sciences
and the criminal justice system. This book is not intended to be a close study of
forensic science, nor was it ever conceived as becoming one. It is devoted to a study
of the judicial response to uses of forensic science in the investigation, prosecution,
and defense of a crime. The audience to which this study is directed are those
intimately or potentially involved in that relationship: police, forensic scientists,
prosecutors, defense lawyers, and professors and students of the criminal law. It is
meant to stand on its own but also to complement the growing number of excellent
treatises and studies in the forensic sciences proper, many of which are published
in the CRC Press series in the area of forensic sciences.
The book focuses on those cases questioning the legal acceptability under a
Frye or Daubert standard of the methodological basis of the forensic science at
issue. However, equally, if not more importantly, the focus is on the discussions of
the numerous cases where the courts, assuming the acceptability of the underlying
methodology, have scrutinized and accepted or rejected a wide variety of investigative uses of the science under discussion, offered as proof of one or more material
facts in a criminal prosecution. This latter area of study is of equal, if not more
central, importance in understanding the place of forensic science in the criminal
justice system of the 21st century. It is time for another close look at both the body
of claims and the actual expert opinions supplied to the criminal justice system as
we enter the new century. The totally justified attention given rapid DNA developments should not overshadow the ongoing judicial acceptance and use of the more
traditional body of forensic sciences, such as hair, fiber, ballistics, and fingerprints,
some of which have never been fully challenged. The contributions of forensic
science to the criminal justice system have been, and remain, significant.
This book is divided into 12 chapters, most of which, with the exceptions of
Chapters 1, Science, Forensic Science, and Evidence, Chapter 2, Science and the
Criminal Law, and Chapter 12, Epilogue, address the legal profile of a specific
forensic science.
Chapter 1, Science, Forensic Science, and Evidence, briefly analyzes the historical and contemporary context in which legal arguments directed to the adequacy
of the findings of forensic science are conducted. This is a necessary precursor to
the more criminally focused discussion that constitutes the bulk of this book. The
framework of the Frye and Daubert standards for the introduction of scientific
opinion are discussed here, as well as the significant differences that exist when the
legal challenge comes in a civil law forum as opposed to a criminal one.
©2001 CRC Press LLC
Chapter 2, Science and the Criminal Law, provides an overview of the entire
subject of the uses of forensic sciences in the investigation, prosecution, and defense
of criminal cases in U.S. courts. Central topics addressed are the historical and
contemporary relationship between forensic science and proof of crime, the fundamentals of the application of forensic science disciplines to the investigation and
prosecution of a criminal case, the function of probabilistic analysis to that process,
and an extended discussion of the legal aspects of the modern crime scene.
Each of the next nine chapters discusses a specific forensic science discipline:
Chapter 3, Hair Analysis, discusses the court’s response to both class and individual
expert opinions in respect to attempts to connect one or more hairs found at a crime
scene to an individual suspect. This controversial subject sets the analytical framework for the discussions that follow on a wide range of forensic science applications.
Chapter 4, Fiber Analysis, discusses the identification and use of a wide variety of
fiber materials from crime scenes and the processes used to link such materials to
a suspect. Chapter 5, Ballistics and Tool Marks, addresses the subjects of firearms
and projectile identification, the matching of bullets to a weapon, gunshot residue,
tool mark identification, and attempts to match crime scene striations to a tool
associated with a suspect. Chapter 6, Soil, Glass, and Paint, discusses the nature of
soil and glass-shard particle identification and the attempt to connect such materials
with an individual suspect. Chapter 7, Footprints and Tire Impressions, addresses
the identification, photographing, and/or casting of footwear and tire impressions
found at a crime scene, and their association with a suspect. The chapter ends with
a listing of bite mark cases. Chapter 8, Fingerprints, discusses the subject of fingerprint identification procedures and the recent Automated Fingerprint Identification
System (AFIS). Chapter 9, Blood Spatter Analysis, analyzes cases involving the
subject of presumptive testing for blood products as well as the subject of bloodstain
pattern analysis and its importance in many key aspects of crime scene reconstruction
efforts. Chapter 10, DNA Analysis, analyzes the court’s scientific conditions for the
acceptance of identification testimony arising from RFLP, PCR, mitochondrial DNA,
and STR DNA analyses, in addition to the small but growing number of cases and
articles addressing nonhuman DNA testing, in particular, dog, cat, and plant DNA
testimony. Chapter 11, Forensic Anthropology and Entomology, briefly examines
those decisions that utilize the methodologies and findings of these fields as aides
to the investigation and identification of human remains and providing time-of-death
estimates. And, finally, Chapter 12, Epilogue, provides a brief summary note on the
subjects not covered in this book and the major points sought to be made in the
entire work. The book ends with an appendix containing an extensive primer on
how to conduct forensic science and forensic evidence research.
©2001 CRC Press LLC
Acknowledgment
I wish to thank Dean Terri Foster of the DePaul University College of Law, for her
gracious and ongoing support during the research and writing of this book. I also
owe a great debt to friend and colleague James J. Ayres, Adjunct Professor of
Computer Law and my cocreator and codirector of the Center for Law and Science
at DePaul University College of Law. I also wish to express my gratitude to DePaul
students Richard Battle, David Becker, and most recently, Maria Vathes and Laura
Pieper, for their research skills, friendship, and untold hours at the final stages of
this book. Many thanks to Harvey Kane and Becky McEldowney of CRC Press.
Harvey had the faith in the project and Becky has gotten me through it with consistent
friendliness, patience, and good humor. Special thanks must go to my editor, Michele
Berman, for her great help in smoothing out the rough edges of this book.
My greatest debt is to my students in Forensic Evidence over these past 5 years,
for their interest and patience as I developed the content and structure of this book.
It goes without saying that my true reason for accomplishing anything is, as
always, my wife Sidni. Thanks again for everything, not the least of which was
keeping our Newfoundland Beau and our pitbull Buster from trashing my office and
consuming the final draft of this work.
©2001 CRC Press LLC
Dedication
This book is dedicated to the loving memory of my mother
Elizabeth Wolfe and my step-father John Wolfe
©2001 CRC Press LLC
Table of Contents
Chapter 1 Science, Forensic Science, and Evidence
I. Science and the Legal Process
II. Litigation as History
III. Law and Science
IV. Science and the Supreme Court
A. Supreme Court Cases
1. Frye v. United States
2. Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals
3. General Electric v. Joiner
4. Kumho Tire v. Carmichael
B. Science Advisory Boards
V. Conclusion
Research Note
Endnotes
Chapter 2 Science and the Criminal Law
I. Introduction
II. Science and the Criminal Law: Overview
III. Forensic Science and Legal History
IV. Forensic Science and Circumstantial Evidence
A. 18th and 19th Century Case Analyses
V. Forensic Science and Forensic Evidence
VI. Forensic Science, Probability, and the Law
VII. Forensic Science, Forensic Evidence, and the Modern Crime Scene
VIII. Forensic Science and the Criminal Law: A Case Study
A. The Facts
B. The Prosecution’s Forensic Evidence: Hairs and Fibers
and Tire Tracks
C. The Court’s Analysis: Hairs and Fibers and Tire Tracks
IX. Conclusion
Research Note
Endnotes
Chapter 3 Hair Analysis
I. Introduction
II. Recent Case Discussions
III. Conclusion
Endnotes
©2001 CRC Press LLC
Chapter 4 Fiber Analysis
1. Introduction
II. The Wayne Williams Case
III. Other Fiber Analysis Cases
Research Note
Endnotes
Chapter 5 Ballistics and Tool Marks
I. Introduction
II. Weapon Identification
III. Angle of Shot
IV. Bullet Matching
V. Incompetency of Counsel
VI. Wound Analysis and Ballistics
VII. Tool Mark Cases
Research Note
Endnotes
Chapter 6 Soil, Glass, and Paint
I. Introduction
II. Glass Analysis
A. General
B. Glass Analysis Cases
III. Paint Analysis
A. General
B. Paint Analysis Cases
IV. Soil Analysis
A. General
B. Soil Analysis Cases
Research Note
Endnotes
Chapter 7 Footprints and Tire Impressions
I. Introduction
II. Footprints
A. General
B. Footwear Cases
III. Tire Impressions
A. General
B. Tire Impression Cases
IV. Bite Mark Case Listing
Research Note
Endnotes
©2001 CRC Press LLC
Chapter 8 Fingerprints
I. Introduction
II. Fingerprint Cases
III. Lip and Ear Print Impressions
Research Note
Endnotes
Chapter 9 Blood Spatter Analysis
I. Introduction
II. Blood Spatter Cases
Endnotes
Chapter 10 DNA Analysis
I. Introduction
II. Questions Lawyers Need to Ask and Answer
III. DNA Cases
A. Postconviction DNA Testing
B. Samples Voluntarily Given Used in Other Cases
C. RFLP and the Product Rule
D. PCR and STR
E. STR DNA
F. mtDNA
G. Nonhuman DNA
Research Note
Endnotes
Chapter 11 Forensic Anthropology and Entomology
I. Anthropology
II. Forensic Anthropology Cases
III. Entomology: Cases
Endnotes
Chapter 12 Epilogue
Appendix A Primer on Researching Forensic Science
to Get to Forensic Evidence
I. Forensics and Crime Scene Bibliography and Research Sources
A. Overview and History
B. Standard Forensic Science Texts
C. Recommended Periodicals
II. Forensic Information on the Internet
A. Dialog/Westlaw Searching
©2001 CRC Press LLC
B. Forensic Science and Related Web Sites
1. Forensic Sciences
2. Law-Related Sites
3. Medicine-Related Sites
4. Science Sites
Table of Cases
©2001 CRC Press LLC
1 Science, Forensic
Science, and Evidence
A discarded theory remains a theory. There are good theories and bad theoriestheories currently regarded as true by everyone and theories that no one any longer
believes to be true. However, when we reject a matter of fact, we take away its
entitlement to the description: it never was a matter of fact at all.
— Steven Shaplin and Simon Schaffer
Leviathan and the Air Pump (1985)
I. SCIENCE AND THE LEGAL PROCESS
The desire to develop a model for the validation of scientific discoveries and methodology has been a constant struggle since the very early period of modern scientific
thinking, in 17th-century England. Sir Francis Bacon, Lord Chancellor and one of
the fathers of modern scientific thinking, composed a work called the New Atlantis,
wherein he created a mythical institution called Saloman’s House or the College of
the Six Days Work. There, inhabitants were devoted to a serious and widespread
search for the identification of scientific discoveries and to developing rigorous
standards for testing their credibility. A complex system of experts was described
by Bacon whose duties were focused on strict examination of practical results to
serve as the basis for more generally applicable scientific principles.1
Robert Hooke, the early-17th-century inventor of the microscope and an associate of the great experimentalist Sir Robert Boyle, along with Francis Bacon also
recognized the difficulty of finding adequate standards for the testing of scientific
validity, especially in cases of attempts to fashion one uniform set of constructs for
any such task:
[F]or the limits to which our thoughts are confined, are small in respect of the vast
extent of Nature itself; some parts of it are too large to be comprehended, and some too
little to be perceived, and from thence it must follow that not having a full sensation of
the object, we must be very lame and imperfect in our conceptions about it, and in all
the propositions which we build upon it; hence we often take the shadow of things for
the substance, small appearances for good similitudes, similitudes for definitions; and
even many of those, which we think to be the most solid definitions are rather expressions
of our misguided apprehension then of the true nature of the things themselves.2
This concern was at the forefront of efforts by early proponents of observational
science and has remained the core issue in modern science-based civil and criminal
litigation. As noted by authors Steven Shaplin and Simon Schaffer in their excellent
study of the origins of modern scientific thinking, Leviathan and the Air Pump:
©2001 CRC Press LLC
Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life,
3 English experimentalists of the mid-17th
century and afterward rapidly took the position that all that could be expected of
physical knowledge was “probability,” thereby removing the radical distinction
between “knowledge” and “opinion.” Physical hypotheses were provisional and
revisable; assent to them was not obligatory, as it was to mathematical demonstrations; and physical science was, to varying degrees, removed from the realm of the
demonstrative:
The probabilistic conception of physical knowledge was not regarded by its proponents
as a regrettable retreat from more ambitious goals; it was celebrated as a wise rejection
of a failed project. By the adoption of a probabilistic view of knowledge, one could
attain to an approximate certainty and aim to secure legitimate assent to knowledgeclaims. The quest for necessary and universal assent to physical propositions was seen
as inappropriate and illegitimate. It belonged to a “dogmatic” enterprise, and dogmatism
was seen not only as a failure but as dangerous to genuine knowledge.4
Historically then, a central concern in such cases is how the courts fashion a set
of observational and linguistic guidelines to gauge the adequacy of a scientific
opinion that is offered to establish a material fact in a trial.
This old debate has come full circle in the search by modern courts for a onesize-fits-all definition of legally sound scientific methodology that will serve justice
in the increasing and predictably complex product liability and criminal cases of the
next century.
The basic inference-based argument used in modern trials, whether aimed toward
a proffered scientific result or a more routine establishment of an important fact,
has served the law as the primary historical method since the earliest days of legal
systems. The method of persuasion used by the great Roman lawyer and scholar
Cicero remains the primary method of convincing a jury to reach one version of
history rather than another. An argument by Cicero in a murder-patricide case in the
year 80 B.C. could be made today, centered in differing opinions of what the facts
were and how they are to be interpreted:
Sextus Roscius, you say, killed his father. Well, what sort of a person is he then?
Obviously he must be some degenerate youth, who has been corrupted by men of evil
character. On the contrary: he is over forty years old. Well, then, he must be a veteran
cut-throat, a ferocious individual throughly accustomed to committing murders. But
the prosecutor has never even begun to suggest anything of the kind. So I suppose he
must have been driven to his criminal act by extravagant habits, or huge debts, or
ungovernable passions. As regards extravagant living, Erucius himself has already
cleared him of that when he indicated that Sextus hardly ever even attended a party.
Debts? He never had any. Passions? Not much scope for these in a man who, as the
prosecutor himself critically remarked, has always lived in the country, devoting his
time to the cultivation of his lands.5
This will become important here as we discuss the current theory setting forth the
propriety of an expert witnesses opinion and its foundation and the utilization of a
wide variety of forensic sciences in the criminal justice system.
©2001 CRC Press LLC
As noted by the famous historian, Carl Becker:
Let us admit that there are two histories: the actual series of events that once occurred;
and the ideal series that we affirm and hold in memory. The first is absolute and
unchanged—it was what it was whatever we do or say about it; the second is relative,
always changing in response to the increase or refinement of knowledge. The two series
correspond more or less; it is our aim to make the correspondence as exact as possible;
but the actual series of events exists for us only in terms of the ideal series we affirm
and hold in memory. This is why I am forced to identify history with knowledge of
history. For all practical purposes history is, for us and for the time being, what we
know it to be.6
Becker’s observation could equally apply to any factual search in litigation, not the
least of which are efforts to establish scientific facts that will be determinative of
the central issues in contemporary environmental, product liability, medical malpractice, and criminal prosecutions. The subject of inference-, probabilistics-, statistics-, and extrapolation-based testimony will be discussed in depth later in this
book. Suffice to say here, that in the extensive area of causation theory and forensic
science and forensic evidence, the history question continues to be a major component in any analysis of proof of scientific fact.
The ultimate goal of the legal process is not to find absolute truth. Any system
that allows a jury to reach a verdict of guilty or not guilty in such important matters
would appear to have something else in mind. The goal of the U.S. litigation system
is to provide the best context, the fairest context, the optimal context, for a jury to
find the truth. This goal of providing the best opportunity for a jury to find its version
of the truth is especially important to understand before entering into extended
discussion of the current preoccupation of the nation’s courts with the science
question.
What is generally acceptable or reliable methodology in various fields that would
justify any opinion, such as the cancer-causing potential of a certain commercial
product? Who determines the answers to this question? What is the scientific
standard to utilize in this inquiry? At what point in the history of a product or a
disputed event and its alleged victim are we to focus? Are civil and criminal cases
sufficiently different in terms of their goals and processes to require different
analyses? Is every opinion that is grounded in some aspect of science subject to
pretrial scrutiny to test the adequacy of the methodology used and the opinion based
upon such use?
Litigation involving questions of science or the nature of the validity of modes
of scientific inquiry has been part and parcel of our legal life since the start of our
national life, beginning in and primarily residing in cases brought up in the nation’s
patent system. In examining the U.S. background to the current preoccupation of
legal scholars and courts in respect to the meaning and application of the term
science in civil and criminal cases, one is struck by the absence of argument on that
point over most of our national life. It is also important to note that the patent laws
were among the earliest laws promulgated by the new U.S. Congress. Thomas
Jefferson was not only a fervent amateur scientist, as was Benjamin Franklin and a
©2001 CRC Press LLC