Thư viện tri thức trực tuyến
Kho tài liệu với 50,000+ tài liệu học thuật
© 2023 Siêu thị PDF - Kho tài liệu học thuật hàng đầu Việt Nam

Evolutionary Microeconomics
Nội dung xem thử
Mô tả chi tiết
! "
!
#"
$
!
!
"
$
! %& '(
)) "
*+ , (
-
.
/
0
1
+!
0
2344)
"
5
6 /-
-
.
/
#
7 879
:;! (
234*:
"
6//-
-
.
/
1 0
+;!
7 #&
23442
"
6 / /-
, (< (
=$
>
( /
! /
! /
8/9/ (! +44+
71#*4 )#3:4#+;3)?#@ 7
A(
1 B
<
71#*) @2;#)#3:4#+;3)?#? 7
A(
1 B
<
0 ##( .
(
- 0
0
1(
C +44?@++;?;
,
< (5
/
!
-
! -
-
!
!
- #
!
! (
!
-
!
( </ . - (
-
- %
0
- 7(
@! *@?3!
!
-
( ( -
7
#D
/ D
( -
%
0
/
7
- 7
7 E
/
F 7
A(
+44?
%
, -
!
!
<! / ( #
! ( - - !
G -
-
-
-
/
A
#. C . H
! A(
71 **3:3:@* :)I)*3)#3 : ) + * 4 J
#-
The authors
Paul Bourgine, research fellow at CREA, Ecole Polytechnique, contributed to chapter 1.
Emmanuelle Fauchart, research fellow at Conservatoire National des
Arts et Métiers, wrote chapter 6.
Jean-François Laslier, research director at CNRS (CECO, Ecole Polytechnique), contributed to chapters 2 and 3.
Jacques Lesourne, professor at Conservatoire National des Arts et Métiers,
fellow of the Econometric Society, wrote chapter 4 and contributed to
introduction and chapter 8.
Luigi Marengo, professor at St. Anna School of Advanced Studies, Pisa,
wrote chapter 7.
François Moreau, professor at Conservatoire National des Arts et Métiers,
wrote chapter 9.
André Orléan, research director CNRS (PSE, CNRS-EHESS-Ecole Normale Supérieure-ENPC), wrote introduction, chapter 5 and contributed
to chapters 2 and 8.
Gisèle Umbhauer, maître de conférences at University of Strasbourg,
contributed to chapter 3.
Bernard Walliser, professor at Ecole Nationale des Ponts et Chaussées
and at Ecole des Hautes Etudes en Sciences Sociales, contributed to
introduction, chapters 1, 3 and 8.
Contents
Introduction........................................................................... 1
The standard paradigm .........................................................................2
Towards an evolutionary paradigm ......................................................6
Presentation of the book .......................................................................7
References ............................................................................................9
Part I: The basic concepts
1 Individual decision........................................................ 13
1.1 Background and problems...........................................................14
1.2 Canonical principles....................................................................22
1.3 Some models ...............................................................................31
1.4 Theses and conjectures................................................................39
References ..........................................................................................41
2 The elementary market................................................. 43
2.1 Background and problems...........................................................43
2.2 Canonical principles....................................................................48
2.3 Some models ...............................................................................50
2.4 Theses and conjectures................................................................64
References ..........................................................................................65
3 Game situations............................................................ 67
3.1 Background and problems...........................................................68
3.2 Canonical principles....................................................................76
3.3 Some models ...............................................................................87
3.4 Theses and conjectures..............................................................108
References ........................................................................................110
VIII Contents
Part II: The markets
4 Market with irreversibilities........................................115
4.1 Background and problems.........................................................116
4.2 Canonical principles..................................................................117
4.3 Some models .............................................................................118
4.4 Theses and conjectures..............................................................128
References ........................................................................................129
5 Mimetic interactions ...................................................131
5.1 Background and problems.........................................................131
5.2 Canonical principles..................................................................140
5.3 Some models .............................................................................147
5.4 Theses and conjectures..............................................................169
References ........................................................................................171
6 Competition between firms ........................................173
6.1 Background and problems.........................................................173
6.2 Canonical principles..................................................................180
6.3 Some models .............................................................................182
6.4 Theses and conjectures..............................................................196
References ........................................................................................198
Part III: The institutions
7 Organization of the firm..............................................203
7.1 Background and problems.........................................................203
7.2 Canonical principles..................................................................205
7.3 Some models .............................................................................207
7.4 Theses and conjectures..............................................................232
References ........................................................................................233
Contents IX
8 Emergence of institutions.......................................... 237
8.1 Background and problems.........................................................237
8.2 Canonical principles..................................................................242
8.3 Some models .............................................................................247
8.4 Theses and conjectures..............................................................256
References ........................................................................................257
9 State and economic system regulation .................... 259
9.1 Background and problems.........................................................259
9.2 Canonical principles..................................................................263
9.3 Some models .............................................................................265
9.4 Theses and conjectures..............................................................282
References ........................................................................................287
Epilogue............................................................................. 291
Introduction
The development of science offers numerous examples of “scientific revolutions” (Kuhn, 1970), which lead to deep changes in the existing “paradigms”. During these revolutions, the prior knowledge, far from being
abandoned since it is obsolete, is often reinterpreted in the new paradigm
as a limit case of a broader representation. The theory of restricted relativity, proposed by A. Einstein, is an exemplary illustration of such a situation. It elaborates a new conception of energy, mass and time breaking up
radically with all was already accepted. Nevertheless, the formula of classical mechanics continues to be valid when considering speeds that are
much lower than the light speed. Is microeconomics involved in such a
revolution and changing its paradigm? One has to be careful when answering such a question since economics is far from being able to claim the
same scientific standards than the hard sciences. Moreover, it is hazardous
to speak of a revolution while it is already on the way.
Even if the conception defended in this book is clearly grounded on a
refoundation of microeconomics, its point of view is more modest. It rests
on four observations: (a) it exists a “standard paradigm” constructed around
three key concepts, optimizing rationality, equilibrium and market efficiency, which frames the main classical works in microeconomics; (b) the
empirical limits of such a paradigm are obvious since it is unable to explain some major observed economic phenomena; (c) several original
models are already available in order to explain at least some of these phenomena; (d) these models express a coherent project, looking as an original paradigm, which integrates standard microeconomics as a limit case.
The book aims at designing this new paradigm, which progressively
emerges at the crossroads of various modeling streams: evolutionary, cognitivist and institutionalist.
Characterized by its departure from classical economics, the present
project has still to be distinguished from another one which inspires today
an important part of microeconomics, the “extended standard theory”
(Favereau, 1989). The last aims at developing the study of organizations
and institutions while staying in the standard paradigm, and is well illustrated by the modern theory of contracts and incentives. The first is interested in institutions too, but is running away from the standard view in
2 Introduction
more profound aspects. However, in order to prevent ambiguity, it is necessary to state that it still shares with the classical or extended approach
number of principles and problems, for instance the adoption of methodological individualism or a specific interest in price formation.
This introduction is devoted to making precise the four statesments
which justify the project. The first section is related to assertions (a) and
(b) and the second to assertions (c) and (d). A third section presents the
structure of the book and its pedagogical aims.
The standard paradigm
The existence of a “standard paradigm” is not unanimously recognized by
economists. As spelt out by R. Nelson and S. Winter (1982, p.6), some
economists “would strenuously deny there is an orthodox position providing
a narrow set of criteria that are conventionally used as a cheap and simple
test for whether an expressed point of view on certain economic questions
is worthy of respect; or, if there is such an orthodoxy, that it is in any way
enforced”. It is right that this notion is mainly put forward by economists
willing to differenciate their work from “normal science”. For that reason,
it may be endowed with a high critical charge which makes it suspicious to
“orthodox” economists. In many cases, it sustains a view which goes beyond a simple objective description of the economists’ achievements in
order to induce a new way of dealing with their discipline. This motivation
is shared by the authors of this book.
One should nevertheless not under-estimate the difficulties associated
with such a goal. Microeconomics is a rapidly developing science which
makes use of various concepts and principles in order to cover an always
broader field. It is not possible to reduce it to a few notions without making a caricature of it. However, it seems possible to bring out what may be
called an “orthodox way” to deal with the usual microeconomic problems.
On one hand, it proceeds to a systematic appeal to optimizing rationality
and equilibrium as two general categories allowing to think all economic
phenomena. On the other hand, it develops a theory of trade order dominated by the assumption of market efficiency. This triptyque will be exploited in order to analyze the standard paradigm.
Optimizing rationality
Adopted by the orthodox approach, optimizing rationality assumes that all
agents are endowed with an objective function that they maximize with re-
The standard paradigm 3
gard to some constraints. It expresses a specific form of instrumental rationality since it deals with the adequation achieved by an agent between the
means at his disposal and the aims he pursues. In order to qualify it,
H. Simon (1982) speaks of “substantive rationality” since it is exclusively
concerned with the results of the choice process. It is opposed to “procedural
rationality” which is mainly interested in the deliberation process leading to
some choice. Optimizing rationality is involved in a lot of economic models such as profit maximization by a firm submitted to technological constraints, (discounted) utility maximization by a consumer trading under a (intertemporal) budget constraint, expected utility maximization by a financial
investor acting under uncertainty and constrained by his initial wealth.
Optimizing rationality is grounded on several implicit assumptions concerning the agent’s cognition when adapting to market exchanges. First,
the agent is always confronted to well defined problems in a transparent
environment. Such an assumption is unrealistic since the agent has to
search for various information in order to make a more precise view of his
environment. He has even to define more accurately what are his own opportunities and preferences since they are not initially given. Second, the
agent is endowed with infinite computing capacities. This is really a distinctive feature of the standard approach: the more the situation is complex, the more are the agents endowed with a sophisticated and performant
rationality. In the limit, all actual interactions between agents are perfectly
simulated by the agents themselves. Such an assumption is again unrealistic
since the agents face computation constraints. Hence, optimizing rationality
appears at best as a contextual limit case, for instance when the agents are
involved in a “small world”.
Equilibrium
In the orthodox view, an equilibrium state is defined as a realizable economic configuration in which no agentw can do better by modifying unilaterally his action. Hence, once an equilibrium state is established, no
agent has an incentive to deviate from it. Such a property explains the importance given to that concept: an equilibrium state tends to survive in the
absence of changing exogenous factors. In other terms, an equilibrium
state is a fixed point of the economic dynamics in a stationary environment. As for optimizing rationality, equilibrium is a general concept which
is illustrated in many specific economic models such as Walrasian competitive equilibrium, Cournot oligopolistic equilibrium, monopoly equilibrium or fixed price equilibrium.
4 Introduction
Although the study of equilibrium states leads to some fundamental results, the orthodox view stays silent about the way an equilibrium state is
reached. The dynamics of what happens out of equilibrium receives little
attention. The Walrasian equilibrium is a good illustration of such a lack of
understanding. Even if the study of its existence and multiplicity has been
fruitfully achieved, and constitutes a powerful achievement of the standard
paradigm, it does not exist a satisfying representation of the exchange
process leading to it. The Walrasian auctioneer device is, in this respect,
very insufficient since it appears as a fictitious entity. In fact, modelling
the off equilibrium process is a fundamental requirement, for instance to
prove that a competitive economy always stays in a neighborhood of some
equilibrium state. Even if it is natural to think that an economy tends to
deviate from any non equilibrium position, it does not follow that it converges naturally toward some equilibrium state. The formal study of dynamical systems concludes to the existence of a great variety of attractors
even when some fixed point exists somewhere. Hence, by lack of a satisfying analysis, nothing proves that a complete flexibility of prices necessarily leads the economic system to a general equilibrium. Moreover, even for
those who stick to the idea that an economy tends to some equilibrium state,
the question of the selection between multiple equilibria is still open. This is
a common situation in contemporary models. In that case, only a dynamical
study is able to select what equilibrium state will prevail as a function of the
initial conditions and the history.
When combining optimizing rationality and equilibrium, one obtains an
abstract view which seems very far from publicly observed features of a
concrete economy. Some orthodox economists were fully aware of that
apparent hiatus. It is the case for M. Friedman (1953) in a famous methodological article entitled “The methodology of positive economics”. Noticing that the orthodox theory is built on assumptions in obvious contradiction with plain observations, he nevertheless defends them. According
to his as if argument, what is important is less the adequation of assumptions to observations than the expectations derived from them. Even if the
actual behaviors may differ from optimizing rationality, everything goes as
if it were valid: the prices and exchanged quantities expected by the model
are in conformity with the observations. Such a methodological position is
called instrumentalist as opposed to realistic since the assumptions are not
choosen for their empirical validity, but are considered as instruments allowing the modeller to infer empirical phenomena. Moreover, M. Friedman and others tried to justify such a position by stressing that non optimizing behaviors may exist, but have a weak impact since the rules of
The standard paradigm 5
competition necessarily lead to their removal. According to these theoreticians, modeling an economy as exclusively formed of maximizing agents
may be instantaneously wrong, but constitutes nevertheless a good approximation in actual economies. However, if it is the evolution process
which produces optimizing behaviors, one has to model it explicitely.
Modeling has to think simultaneously the economic phenomena and the
conditions of their emergence.
Market efficiency
According to the orthodox approach, the competitive market is the fundamental institutional device allowing an efficient resolution of all coordination problems encountered by mutual exchanges. More profoundly, the
competitive equilibrium is endowed with the status of a norm. On one
hand, it constitutes the basic reference for evaluating all other equilibrium
notions. The notion of “market failure” precisely refers to conditions not
satisfied in a competitive market: incomplete information, imperfect competition, sluggish prices. On the other hand, it suggests the way to deal
with any new difficulty. The recommendation is to establish or reestablish
the institutional conditions for obtaining an equivalent of a competitive
equilibrium. For instance, the distribution of “rights to pollute” consists in
creating a new market in order to solve an unusual environmental problem.
Such an approach, even if relevant in some instances, conceals great
dangers and may lead to important biases. On one hand, the obtention of
market efficiency, either allocative or informational, is still an open question and not a dogma. Even when involved with a rigourous proof, as for
Paretian efficiency of a competitive market, it rests on many restrictive assumptions on behaviors as well as on goods. On the other hand, the identification of an economy to markets leads to a distorted view of the trade order. It is wrong to consider the market as a natural entity, as a necessary
by-product of the rationality of mutual exchanges. The market is a peculiar
social construct which needs for coming to maturity a whole set of social
conditions. Observing the evolution of capitalism brings to the fore historical phases in which some markets see their role increase or decline. For instance, during the Thirty Glorious years in France, the stock market had a
marginal impact. Besides, the competitive forces always coexist with other
forms of regulation of same importance, for instance money, hierarchical
links, trust, conventions and norms. The prevalence given to the market
leads to under-estimate the regulative function of other entities, which act
conjointly with the market, for instance the firm, the central bank or the law.
6 Introduction
Towards an evolutionary paradigm
To the triptyque formed by optimizing rationality, equilibrium and market
efficiency, the promoted approach opposes procedural rationality, dynamic
processes and plurality of institutions. Hence, it is situated at the junction
of several modeling streams which developed with some success these last
three categories, namely the cognitivist, evolutionnist and institutionalist
approaches. If the term “evolutionary” is chosen to qualify that synthesis,
it is not only due to the necessity of a simple denotation, but also to the
transversal role played by that notion in the structuration of the set of approaches. As was already stressed, the underlying epistemology of our approach, at odds with Friedmanian individualism, insists on an evolutionary
modelling of the processes at work, simultaneously cognitive when individual decision-making is concerned, evolutionist when dynamic interactions are concerned and self-organizational when institutions are introduced. The federating role played by the evolution processes in our
analysis explains why the labelling “evolutionist paradigm” is favored1
.
It is obvious that the conceptual achievement of evolutionary economics
would have been impossible without the constitution of a set of technical
tools allowing for a renewed approach of the economic evolution. For instance, with the mathematical study of non linear dynamic systems, one
gets a lot of new concepts and results concerned with stability, bifurcations
and various forms of attractors. Likely, with the formal work by physicists
on systems of heterogeneous and tightly related entities, one gets richer insights about “self-organization” (Lesourne, 1991) or “emergent phenomena”. Finally, with the development of epistemic logics by philosophers
and cognitive scientists, one gets a more accurate view of individual (and
collective) beliefs and modes of reasoning.
Despite some external influences, the central theses of the book belong
really to economic science, or more generally to social sciences. They induce a conception of economics notably different of the conception which
prevails in traditional textbooks. This can be illustrated by three examples
1
Note however that what the research program called here ‘evolutionary economics’ is not far from what B. Walliser calls elsewhere ‘cognitive economics’
(2000). Conversely, it differs from economic models called ‘evolutionary’ in a
strict sense and focalized on a dynamic dimension without replacing it in a cognitive and institutional framework. It differs even more with an approach exclusively grounded on a biological analogy as evolution is concerned.
Presentation of the book 7
which depart more and more from the traditional view of an efficient market equilibrium. First, the notion of “path dependency” will be frequently
used in order to stress that “history matters”. The state towards which the
economic system may converge depends on the internal events that happened along its path and on the external shocks that perturbed its trajectory. Such a notion is not incompatible with an equilibrium analysis, but it
restricts its relevance since that analysis has to be completed. Second, the
evolutionary dynamics does not necessarily converge towards some optimal state. Contrary to the common vulgate shared by some evolutionnists,
evolution does not systematically mimic a global optimization of the system. Not only is the asymptotic state not collectively optimal in some
technical sense, but the notion of optimality becomes even problematic.
Third, it appears that in many situations, the attractors are not necessarily
punctual. The system may stay perpetually in a moving state, and the notion of equilibrium looses its relevance. This is the case when observing
limit cycles or chaotic dynamics.
These contributions of evolutionary economics stay compatible with a
somewhat mecanist approach of economic evolution. The introduction
both of beliefs and institutions is a further step which improves even
more the proposed analysis. Especially, it is shown that the beliefs have a
proper efficiency since the coordination of individuals depends on how
each agent interprets his strategic environment. Likely, the institutional
devices influence in several ways the interaction process by coordinating
the agents’ beliefs as well as actions. The complex interwaving of these
factors leads to an image of economic dynamics which is conceptually
better fitted to the economic phenomena and is pragmatically better
adapted to the economic problems.
Presentation of the book
The book differs profoundly from preceding books dealing with evolutionary economics too (Witt, 1992; Hodgson, 1996; Schweitzer-Silberberg,
1998; Dopfer, 2001; Foster-Metcalfe, 2001; Gandolfi et alli, 2002; Backhaus, 2003; Witt, 2003). These books are litterary presentations of evolutionary economics or proceedings of conferences on the topic. The structure of the present book in three parts manifests a progression from the
presentation of basic concepts to the analysis of complex situations. In
fact, it follows more or less the structure in traditional textbooks.